AMERICANISM: STRONGHOLD OF HEGEL
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling (2013–2018)
THE NEW HEGELIAN ORTHODOXY
Turn your backs upon methodology: Gangrene is never cured with Lavender water. Hegel¹
The supremacy of the American world and the birth of Global rational political and economic order is the handiwork of the 21st century, and is now well under way: Globalism is therefore world civilization, the ultimate phase of which is therefore Americanism.
The mortal enemies of the American world do not accept this verdict of exact historiography and universal history: Even today they fight tooth–and–nail against the floodtide of American political and economic rationality in the world. The mortal enemies of Americanism are therefore the destroyers of the developmental unification and coaxial integration of the American world:
“The Kantian philosophy thus serves as a cushion for intellectual indolence which soothes itself with the conviction that everything is already proved and settled.”²
We know the results of 20th century political and economic irrationalism in the disintegration of modernity and its inferior ruling classes: “Kant’s philosophy is a high one … the march of God in the world, that is what the state is.”³ The world historical ground of modernity is thus utterly swept–away in the rise of Globalism and the superior ruling class.
Modern irrationalism, in order to validate pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism, squares the Lecture Notes and the great works published by Hegel in his lifetime.⁴ Pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism thus squares both Kant and Hegel in order to prove the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of Absolute Idealism is flawed.⁵ Irrationalism thus perverts the history of philosophy and modern Europe, especially that of the 20th century:
“If Hegel … had been led to talk more about social needs and less about Absolute Knowledge, Western philosophy might … have saved itself a century of nervous shuffles.”⁶
Pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism is therefore the political and economic mask of modern European Raison d’État.⁷ One drawback will never be remedied in Hegel philology: The Lecture Notes are not authoritative and are therefore useless in the exact determination of the ultimate worth of genuine Hegelianism.
“[Hegel] was a thoroughly anti–critical, anti–revolutionary philosopher … Hegel’s teaching had been taken up by the Left in a one–sided and abstract way; and the great majority of people always prefer what one can become fanatical about, and this is never anything but what is abstract.”⁸
The great ship of modernity is sinking and the irrationalists are going down …
In the 20th century upwards of 500 million human beings were slaughtered in the contagion of modern political and economic satanism, more than in all the periods of history combined: Many hundreds of millions more were utterly ruined and destroyed by the most barbaric slavery ever recorded in the world.⁹ This is the ultimate verdict of exact historiography and universal history.¹⁰ From whence comes the disease of modern unreason?
“All things that exist being particulars … every man’s reasoning and knowledge is only about the ideas existing in his own mind.”¹¹
Thus, the world does not exist, according to John Locke, while the universe is appearance and delusion.¹² Locke’s irrationalism proved deadly in the arena of modern European politics and economics, especially in the 20th century:
“Nothing in the world is eternal,” says Joseph Stalin, “everything in the world is transient and mutable; nature changes, society changes, habits and customs change, conceptions of justice change, truth itself changes … our conceptions, our ‘self,’ exist only in so far as external conditions exist that give rise to impressions in our ‘self.’”¹³
Leibniz, Hume, and Kant as well as their schools are guilty of the selfsame sophistry: “Hegel’s spirit was sufficiently broad to contain, among its disciples, the most various and even contradictory tendencies. He was great, on the one hand by his metaphysical results, on the other by his logical method; on the one hand as the crown of dogmatic philosophy, on the other as the founder of the dialectic, with its then revolutionary doctrine of historical development. Both these aspects of Hegel’s work revolutionized thought, but in their practical bearing they diverged widely. While the practical tendency of his metaphysics was, and is, to glorify existing institutions, to see in Church and State the objective embodiment of the Absolute Idea, his dialectic method tended to exhibit no proposition as unqualified truth, no state of things as final perfection … to Hegel, the reality of the world is only thought, the logical development of thought, from the simplest to the most complex forms, must reproduce itself in the historical development of things. The validity of this view we need not here examine; it is sufficient to point out that [5] Hegel, in his ‘Philosophy of History,’ endeavored to exhibit the actual course of the world as following the same necessary chain of development which, as it exists in thought, forms the subject of his logic. In this development, everything implies, and even tends to become, its opposite, as son implies father; the development of the world therefore proceeds by action and reaction, or, in technical language, by thesis and antithesis, and these become reconciled in a higher unity, the synthesis of both … we might live to see another French Revolution, perhaps even more glorious than the first, leaving Social Democracy to try one of the greatest and most crucial experiments in political history.”¹⁴
We might live to see another French Revolution, perhaps even more glorious than the first: “To Hegel, the life process of the human brain is the demiurgos of the real world, and the real world is only the external, phenomenal form of ‘the Idea’ … it [the Hegelian Dialectic] includes in its comprehension and affirmative recognition of the existing state of things, at the same time also, the recognition of the negation of that state, of its inevitable breaking up; because it [the Hegelian Dialectic] regards every historically–developed social form as in fluid movement, and therefore takes into account its transient nature not less than its momentary existence; because it [the Hegelian Dialectic] lets nothing impose upon it, and is in its essence critical and revolutionary.”¹⁴
The rational dialectic of Hegel is in its essence critical and revolutionary? “The philosophy of Hegel is the algebra of revolution, it emancipates man to an extraordinary degree and leaves not a stone standing of the Christian world, of the world of outlived tradition.”¹⁵ Indeed, the two–headed beast of American irrationalism, the satanic creature of Chomskyism and Rortyism, leaves a path of intellectual destruction in its wake as it crawls on its crocodile–like paws, Russell, Wittgenstein, and Carnap on the one side, with Gödel, Tarski, and Popper on the other, while its filth encrusted Quinean and Kripkean tail slithers along behind.¹⁶
These modern European gentlemen, and they were not alone, reasoned about a part of the rational world, under the delusion that it is the whole of rationality, and thus they did not reason about the world at all: “When I hear the name ‘Hitler,’ I do feel it’s sort of analytic that the man was evil. But really, probably not. Hitler might have spent all his days in quiet in Linz … I say that a designator is rigid, and designates the same thing in all possible worlds.”¹⁷
Thus they became the victims of their own folly: Thus they fell prey to far greater reasoners. Certainly, it is not the case the realm of ultimate logical and linguistic reality is unintelligible and that something unknowable exists: “The ultimate ground of logic is the realm of truth without veil, the system of pure reason and the world of pure thought.”¹⁸
Destroyer of language and logic, grandiose corrupter of the American Spirit, the political and economic diabolism of Chomskyism and Rortyism is thus forever banned from the Sacred Halls of Americanism: “Thou Shall Not Pass Here,” is inscribed upon the uppermost chambers of American Raison d’État.¹⁹
“The United States … imposes intolerable regimes on Asian, Latin American, and Middle East countries, and economically exploits the great majority of mankind who live at below–subsistence level to support American profit … The American government pursues a policy of genocide.”²⁰
Certainly, it is not the case the realm of ultimate political and economic reality is unintelligible and that something unknowable exists: “The concrete Ideas, the minds of the nations, have their truth and their destiny in the concrete Idea which is absolute universality, i.e., in the world mind … as mind, it is nothing but its active movement towards absolute knowledge of itself.”²¹
All decline and decay in American civilization is therefore irrationalism: “Catholicism is the oldest and greatest totalitarian movement in history,” babbles Sidney Hook, “other totalitarian movements have borrowed from it … [Christianity] can never be applied.”²² All that is therefore mortally corrupt in America bears the rotten hallmark of modern irrationalism:
“If they do it it’s terrorism, if we do it it’s counter–terrorism. That’s an historical universal: Go back to Nazi propaganda the most extreme mass murders ever. If you look at Nazi propaganda, it’s exactly what they said: They said they are defending the populations and the legitimate governments of Europe like Vichy from the terrorist partisans who are directed from London, that’s the basic propaganda line … We did it therefore it’s a just cause: You can read that in the Nazi archives too.”²³
“It is not mere chance that the greatest philosopher of experimental empiricism — John Dewey — is also the greatest philosopher of democracy.”²⁴ Long ago, therefore, the Idealistic Spirit of a youthful and vibrant America in the firmament of great civilizations, was utterly debased by the sophistry of American philosophical irrationalism: It is the selfsame decadence that destroyed Old Europe in a firestorm of unreason, in the so–called modern democracies of liberalism, republicanism, nationalism, socialism and communism, — in the power of the people and the tyranny of the masses, in the contagion of the political and economic satanism of the 20th century:
“Logic, in the Hegelian use, is just that criterion of truth which we thought at first to find in Kant’s transcendental Logic … [Hegel] offers us Reason affirmative and negative, and affirmative only in and through its own negations.”²⁵
The New World is the greatest civilization in history because American Idealism is the Spirit of Americanism: American Idealism is the philosophy of Western civilization in the present age, the Spirit of rational political and economic order in the world: Roosevelt was a cripple; he was a physical weakling; he was a man with no legs; but his profound genius, his unswerving devotion to the cause of America, uplifted the American civilization to the heights of world power. Joseph Stalin, on the other hand, the man of steel, was a brawler, a thug, a hardened criminal and a cold–hearted killer: Stalin and Hitler sealed the fate of Europe and unleashed a floodtide of satanism that engulfed half the earth in a firestorm of unreason. The Spiritual development of American civilization is the political and economic progress of humanity in the world, the result of the systematic and ruthless destruction of barbarism: This is also the ultimate verdict of the exact historiography and history of Westernism in the 20th century. Certainly, it is not the case the realm of ultimate reality is unintelligible and that something unknowable exists: “What is rational is actual, and what is actual is rational.”²⁶
The disintegration of modern European civilization in a floodtide of irrationalism, culminating in the collapse of Old Europe and the political and economic satanism of the 20th century, has absolutely nothing to do with the true and real spirit of science and technology in the world of today. It is rather the sophistry of the modern irrationalists: Locke, Leibniz, Hume and Kant.²⁷ “What other movement can hold up a positive ideal of equality in freedom which can simultaneously give hope to millions and shake the ideological foundations of totalitarianism?”²⁸ From whence comes this contagion of modern political and economic unreason?
The clash between East versus West unleashed the plague of irrationalism and the spiritual degeneration of modern Europe in the warfare of civilization versus barbarism, which is therefore also the titanic struggle between reason and unreason in the world: “Their deeds and destinies in their reciprocal relations to one another are the dialectic of the finitude of these minds, and out of it arises the universal mind, the mind of the world, free from all restriction, producing itself as that which exercises its right — and its right is the highest right of all — over these finite minds in the ‘history of the world which is the world’s court of judgement.’”²⁹
In the Empire of Paul Desmarais, all modern Canadian political and economic distinctions between liberalism, conservatism and socialism are therefore become merely relative, and therefore their notion is become outdated in the rational development of the Absolute in world history, and therefore the old political and economic conception of Canada is undone and yet also overcome in the period of the Québec Regime in Ottawa, 1968–2006.³⁰ Ottawa is now the first sphere of Americanism: The Québec Regime therefore signalizes the end of modern European Raison d’État in Canada, — in the world historical sublation of Global civilisation.³¹ The selfsame political and economic rationality of Americanism is also evidenced in every other region of the 20th century, in the rise of the American world: In the Empire of Desmarais the old conception of Canada is therefore undone, but within the world historical realm of Globalism is yet also overcome …
The aggrandizement of the Western Spirit in the Global rational political and economic order of American civilisation and the abolition of barbarism in the world is therefore the true and real spiritual power of the sciences, philosophy and history, as well as religion, literature and the arts.
The Idea of America and the rational distinction between Americanism and anti–Americanism in the world of today is therefore the result of the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes in the political and economic arena of 20th century world history: “Of all the disciplines, the study of the folly and achievements of man is best calculated to help develop the critical sense of what is permanent and meaningful amid the mass of superficial and transient events and decisions which engulf the presidency.”³²
The separation of the wheat from the chaff is therefore the work of the greatest American Idealists: Wilson, Roosevelt, Truman, Eisenhower, Kennedy, Johnson, Nixon, Ford, Carter, Reagan, Bush the Elder, Clinton, Bush the Younger and Obama, to name but a few…
Americanism is therefore the spiritual journey of humanity in the world historical realm of rational political and economic order: Globalism is thus the end of world history and the birth of Cosmism. This is the ultimate secret of Americanism in the world of today.³³
American Idealists of the earth unite under the banner of Americanism in the world!
CHAPTER 1: MODERN ENEMIES OF PLATO AND HEGEL
Why don’t the moderate liberals state that, if the Government continues their socialism and arbitrary ways, they cannot support them?
Edward VII, 1910¹
Now the Kantian traditions have gained power once more.
Ernst Mach, Vienna, 1912²
The [Russian] Revolution is the greatest service which they have yet made to the cause for which the Allied peoples have been fighting since August 1914 … this war is at bottom a struggle for popular Government as well as for liberty.
David Lloyd George³
Plato is a noologist: “[Plato] has expressed for all time the perfect exemplar of the rationalistic temper.”⁴ What exactly does modern sophistry, especially in the 20th century, mean by “noologism” and the “rationalistic temper” of Plato with regards to the philosophy of Hegel? “Hegel’s metaphysical doctrine of the State bears a resemblance, which is not accidental, to the Platonic metaphysics of nature.”⁵ In other words, according to the modern sophists, Hegel is a Platonist: “[Hegel’s] doctrine that the State is the product of a timeless process, of which the stages stand to one another in a relation of logical consequence, is a relic of Platonism in his metaphysics.”⁶ According to the modern sophists, the metaphysics of Hegel is a relic of Platonism. What is the crime of Plato and Platonism in the scatology of modern irrationalism?
“The failure of Greek ethics to achieve a notion of will was a necessary consequence of Greek metaphysics. The essence of this metaphysics was the distinction within the universe of an intelligible nature from a sensible nature, the former being the ground, or ratio essendi, of the latter … [Hegel] makes the distinction between the ‘idea’ and its historical manifestation precisely analogous to the Platonic distinction between the intelligible and the sensible within the world of physical nature.”⁷
Hegel, according to the sophists, is guilty of the charge of Platonism, which is the philosophical crime of dogmatic metaphysics: “The Hegelian doctrine that it [the state] is to be understood only as the product of a logical development appears, and is, uncompromisingly Platonic.”⁸ The evidence of Hegel’s guilt of the crime of Platonic metaphysics is his Platonic logic: “[Hegel] gives to the state as it exists in the world a status in the scale of being which Plato was bound in consistency to reserve for the idea ‘laid up in heaven.’”⁹ The logic of Hegel and Plato are the same: “For Hegel the earthly realization of the state involves no admixture of the idea with an alien element, but is no less than the development of the idea itself, the earthly state possesses undiminished the status of being which Plato assigned to the idea.”¹⁰
What exactly is, according to the modern sophists, the criminal nature of the logic of Hegel and Plato in the arena of politics and economics? “The institutions of parliamentary democracy, of which it is the proper function to be organs (not the enforcement, but) of the creation of the law, can find no place in Hegel’s State.”¹¹ Modern sophists thus accuse Hegel of anti–democracy: “The franchise of the citizen of a parliamentary democracy does not confer a right either to rule or to participate in the activity of ruling; it confers the right to take part in the quite different activity, proper not to the ruler but to a sovereign, of commanding the laws which the ruler has to enforce. This freedom is totally lacking in Hegel’s State.”¹²
The Hegel of the modern sophists is not alone in his political and economic barbarism: “Since indeed he [Hegel] lacks the conception of will as creative, he is bound, like Plato, to regard any exercise of will upon the law as perversive of its nature.”¹³ Thus, according to the modern sophists, Hegel and Plato are the forefathers of 20th century totalitarianism: Sophists, we must conclude, are therefore the progenitors of modern political and economic rationality, while philosophers are the promoters of political and economic unreason. In other words, the philosophers are sophists, while the sophists are philosophers!
Thus, the crime of Hegel, according to the modern sophists, is nothing more than the Hegelian rejection and opposition to modern European raison d’État: “When Hegel elucidates his conception of the State by contrast with Kant or the political theories of modern Empiricism, he refers to the Greek Polis, of which he takes Plato’s Republic to be the ideal representation, as that of all forms of society in which the nature of the State is most closely anticipated.”¹⁴ The modern sophists are indeed correct, the Pure Hegel is the avowed enemy of modern political and economic irrationalism, but they are absolutely incorrect in the identification of Pure Hegelism with sophistry: “Hegel perverts the truth which he purports to be ‘translating into the concept.’”¹⁵ Hegel is therefore guilty of sophistry?
“[Hegel] can conceive of no virtue in practical activity except in so far as it is governed by a concept, so he can conceive no process to be intelligible which is not teleological. If human history is a teleological process, then it is to be rendered intelligible by a conception of its end distinct from the empirical description of the events which are means to its achievement. Thus Hegel is led inevitably to his vicious distinction of Philosophy of History from the empirical science of history, the former having as its object the end, the latter the means of the historical process.”¹⁶
Hegel is led inevitably to his vicious distinction of Philosophy of History from the empirical science of history? Hegel, according to the modern sophists, suffers from the vice of vicious distinction. The empirical science of history is viciously opposed to Hegel’s Philosophy of History, which involves the end and not the means of the historical process:
“The vice of this distinction is now so universally recognized that further exposure of it may be spared. I am indebted specially to Croce’s forceful criticisms of the doctrine. I need hardly add that Hegel’s own practice often enough belies his theory and that there is much great History in what he [Hegel] calls his Philosophy of History.”¹⁷
Pray tell, what exactly does the Pure Hegel call his Philosophy of History? Is there much great History in the Lectures on the Philosophy of History written and published by Eduard Gans? Is there much great History in the Lectures on the History of Philosophy written and published by Carl Ludwig Michelet? Is there much great History in the Lectures on the Philosophy of History written and published by Karl Ritter von Hegel? Is there much great History in Hegel’s philosophy of history found in the originalausgabe? Without the rational argument in favor of the exact distinctions between the empirical and non–empirical science of history found in the works of Hegel, as well as between scientific and pseudo–scientific historiography, the modern sophistical attack against the Pure Hegel falls flat: In other words, Hegel is a sophist, according to British Empiricists like Michael Beresford Foster, because according to Benedetto Croce, Hegel is a sophist!
What exactly does Signor Croce have to say about Hegel? “No one but Hegel has understood Kant … in the History of Philosophy also, Hegel attained to heights never reached previously to him and rarely since … [Hegel] sought to adapt to his dialectic universal history as it appears in the books of the historians; and he deluded himself that he had found in the individual a point of departure which should have the precision of the first term of the dialectic triad … The triadic expedient, and the term Logos, to which Hegel has recourse, show that he is always entangled in dualism; that he struggles valiantly against it, but does not escape from it. This dualism not overcome, in which Hegel’s absolute idealism becomes entangled, owing to the grave logical error he has committed.”¹⁸ Hegel suffered from delusions and committed a grave logical error (Hegel was truly a Kantian), according to Benedetto Croce, the father of Italian Hegelianism, after Augusto Véra.
But which Hegel is this, the Hegel of Benedetto Croce, Michael Beresford Foster and British Empiricism? Why, it is the Hegel of the pseudo–Hegelians and anti–Hegelians: “The State as it is in the present is the product of a teleological process, of which the end was not conceived by any of the human agents whose acts were the means of its achievement.”¹⁹ Wherefore?
“This process is the process of World–history as it has unfolded itself up to the present time. It is a development, in that it is directed towards an end, and it is a natural development, in that the end is that of the ‘Weltgeist’ or World Spirit, which uses the human agents of history as unconscious tools to its achievement, and which thus stands to them in somewhat the same relation as the divine Demiurge to processes of growth in nature. To be used thus by the World Spirit as a means to its end is what constitutes the historical importance of a people or of an event and the greatness of an individual.”²⁰
Where, pray tell, is it exactly in the Pure Hegel that the State as it is in the present is the product of a teleological process, of which the end was not conceived by any of the human agents whose acts are and were the means of its achievement, namely, where is it exactly in the Pure Hegel that the process of world history as it unfolds and has unfolded itself up to the present time, is a development, directed towards an end, a natural development, in that the end is that of the “Weltgeist” or World Spirit, which uses all the human agents of history as unconscious tools to its achievement? The basis of the so–called Hegelian vice of vicious distinction, by which Hegel is classified as a sophist by the modern irrationalists, is extracted from the works of impure Hegelianism:
“This is the famous doctrine of ‘Die List der Vernunft.’ See §298 Zusätze for an illustration of how the selfish and ambitious acts of historical personages are turned to an end of which they had no conception. In §344 the ‘states, peoples, and individuals’ who do the business of the World Spirit are called ‘bewußtlose Werkzeuge,’ and in §348 it is explicitly declared that the work which they do ‘is concealed from them and is not their object or purpose.’”²¹
Hegel is rejected as a sophist by Benedetto Croce and British Empiricists like Michael Beresford Foster in virtue of material culled from the works of impure Hegelianism: Modern irrationalists ignore and neglect the rational distinction between the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism on the one hand, and the pseudo–Hegel of impure Hegelianism on the other. Is it really and truly the case that the selfish and ambitious acts of all historical personages are turned to an end of which they have and had no conception, namely, does the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism teach or “explicitly declare” that the work which all states, nations, and individuals do “is concealed from them and is not their object or purpose”?
“States, nations, and individuals [die Staaten, Völker und Individuen in diesem Geschäfte des Weltgeistes] arise animated by their particular determinate principle which has its interpretation and actuality in their constitutions and in the whole range of their life and condition. While their consciousness is limited to these and they are absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind at work within them. The shapes which they take pass–away, while the absolute mind prepares and works out its transition to its next higher stage.”²²
The Pure Hegel: States, nations, and individuals (die Staaten, Völker und Individuen in diesem Geschäfte des Weltgeistes), namely, civilizations, arise animated by their particular, determinate principle which has its interpretation and actuality in their constitutions and in the whole range of their life and condition. While the consciousness of civilizations is limited to these, and while they are absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: The shapes which they take pass–away, while the absolute mind prepares and works out its transition to its next higher stage.
What does this mean according to the Pure Hegel? While the consciousness of civilizations is limited to these, namely, the particular, determinate principle which has its interpretation and actuality in their constitutions and in the whole range of their life and condition, and while they are not absorbed in their mundane interests, they are not all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind. Thus, some of the shapes which the consciousness of civilizations takes, do not pass–away, and the absolute mind prepares and works out its transition to its next higher stage. What is in question here is the nature of the Dialectic of Hegel:
“The history of a single world–historical nation contains (a) the development of its principle from its latent embryonic stage until it blossoms into the self–conscious freedom of ethical life and presses in upon world history; and (b) the period of its decline and fall, since it is its decline and fall that signalizes the emergence in it of a higher principle as the pure negative of its own. When this happens, mind passes over into the new principle and so marks out another nation for world–historical significance.”²³
The absolute mind prepares and works out its transition to its next higher stage, namely, decline and fall signifies the emergence of a higher principle as the pure negative: While the consciousness of civilizations is absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind. While the consciousness of civilizations is not absorbed in their mundane interests, they are not all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: The history of a single world historical civilization contains the development of its principle from its latent embryonic stage until it blossoms into the self–conscious freedom of ethical life and presses in upon world history. What does this mean?
“All actions, including world–historical actions, culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial, they are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind and they are therefore directly at one with that deed though it is concealed from them and is not their aim and object.”²⁴
All actions, says the Pure Hegel, including world historical actions, culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial, namely, while the consciousness of civilizations is absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind and they are therefore directly at one with that deed and it is concealed from them and is not their aim and object.
All actions, says the Pure Hegel, including world historical actions, culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial, namely, while the consciousness of civilizations is not absorbed in their mundane interests, they are not all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind and they are therefore directly at one with that deed and it is not concealed from them and is their aim and object.
World historical individuals and actions, therefore, are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind, and some of them are therefore directly at one with that deed, and it is not therefore concealed from some of them, and it is their aim and object. Wherefore? The historical development of the principle of Western civilization blossoms into the self–conscious freedom of ethical life in world history: World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind, and some of them are directly at one with that deed, and it is not concealed from them as their aim and object, — as the historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life in world history.
The deed of the world mind is the historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life in world history: The dialectic of universal history is therefore the principle of the historical development of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life, namely, world civilization. World historical individuals and actions are therefore the living instruments of the historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life as world civilization: World historical individuals are the living instruments of the dialectic of world history. The historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life is in substance the deed of the world mind, namely, as individual subjects giving actuality to the substantial, from the embryonic stage until it blossoms: They are not therefore absorbed in their mundane interests, they are therefore all the time the conscious tools and organs of the mind of the world.
The genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism says of those individuals who are directly at one with the deed of the world mind although it is concealed from them and is not their aim and object:
“For the deeds of the world mind, therefore, they receive no honour or thanks either from their contemporaries or from public opinion in later ages. All that is vouchsafed to them by such opinion is undying fame in respect of the subjective form of their acts.”²⁵
World historical actions culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial in respect of the subjective form of their acts as inferior ruling classes, namely, the emergence of a higher principle as the pure negative. For this very reason the deed of the world mind is concealed from them, and is not their aim and object. The morphology of the text proves that §348 continues the thought at the end of both §347 and §347A, which means that Hegel is referring in §348 to the topic directly above, namely, to the distinction between the rise and fall of civilizations in both §347 and §347A, “in the advance of the self–developing self–consciousness of the world mind,” but in the negative dimension, namely, “in contrast with this its absolute right of being the vehicle of this present stage in the world mind’s development.” According to the Pure Hegel:
“World–history, however, is above the point of view [Gesichtspunkten] from which these things matter. Each of its stages is the presence of a necessary moment in the Idea of the world mind, and that moment attains its absolute right in that stage.”²⁶
All the stages present the necessary moments in the idea of the world mind, and all the moments attain their absolute right in all the stages of world history: “The nation whose life embodies this moment secures its good fortune and fame, and its deeds are brought to fruition.”²⁷ The life of world civilization thus embodies all the moments, and is the deed of all, brought to fruition:
“The mind which has thus reverted to the substantiality with which it began is the mind which has returned out of the infinite opposition, and which consequently engenders and knows this its truth as thought and as a world of actual laws.”²⁸
Therefore, out of the dialectic of finitude of Pure Hegelism arises the universal mind of the world, and therefore the historical development of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life is in substance the deed of the world mind, namely, as individual subjects giving actuality to the substantial, from the embryonic stage until it blossoms: They are not therefore absorbed in their mundane interests, they are therefore all the time the conscious tools and organs of the world mind. They are therefore the superior ruling classes.
Thus, the Pure Hegel is the modern philosophical progenitor of the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes. What is the nature of superior ruling classes? All actions, including world historical actions, culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial, namely, when the consciousness of civilizations is not absorbed in mundane interests, they are not all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind and they are therefore directly at one with that deed and it is not concealed from them and is their aim and object:
“The history of a single world–historical nation [eines welthistorischen Volks] contains (a) the development of its principle from its latent embryonic stage until it blossoms into the self–conscious freedom of ethical life and presses in upon world history.”²⁹
The historical development of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life is in substance the deed of the world mind, namely, as individual subjects giving actuality to the substantial, from the embryonic stage until it blossoms. They are not therefore absorbed in their mundane interests, they are therefore all the time the conscious tools and organs of the world mind: They are the superior ruling classes. What is the world historical nature of these superior ruling classes of rising civilization (eines welthistorischen Volks)?
“Each of its stages is the presence of a necessary moment in the Idea of the world mind, and that moment attains its absolute right in that stage. The nation whose life embodies this moment secures its good fortune and fame, and its deeds are brought to fruition.”³⁰
The superior ruling class is a necessary moment in the Idea of the world mind, and attains its absolute right at that stage in the advancement of Western civilization in universal history:
“The nation to which is ascribed a moment of the Idea in the form of a natural principle is entrusted with giving complete effect to it in the advance of the self–developing self–consciousness of the world mind. The nation is dominant in world history [das Herrschende] during this one epoch, and it is only once that it can make its hour strike.”³¹
The civilization to which is ascribed a moment of the Idea in the form of a natural principle is entrusted with giving complete effect to it, and is dominant in world history during this one epoch, and it is only once that it can make its hour strike: The advancement of the self–developing self–consciousness of the world mind is the work of the superior ruling classes of Western civilization. The dialectic of world history, which is the principle of the historical development of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life, according to the Pure Hegel, is the advancement of the self–developing self–consciousness of the world mind as the superior ruling class of Western civilization:
“The history of mind is its own act. Mind is only what it does, and its act is to make itself the object of its own consciousness. In history its act is to gain consciousness of itself as mind, to apprehend itself in its interpretation of itself to itself. This apprehension is its being and its principle, and the completion of apprehension at one stage is at the same time the rejection of that stage and its transition to a higher. To use abstract phraseology, the mind apprehending this apprehension anew, or in other words returning to itself again out of its rejection of this lower stage of apprehension, is the mind of the stage higher than that on which it stood in its earlier apprehension.”³²
Why do the superior ruling classes affect the work of mind, “returning to itself again out of its rejection of this lower stage of apprehension”? Why do the superior ruling classes affect the work of mind on the “stage higher than that on which it stood in its earlier apprehension”? The work of the superior ruling classes is “mind apprehending this apprehension anew,” as the mortal enemy of all inferior ruling classes:
“But to those who reject this doctrine, mind has remained an empty word, and history a superficial play of casual, so–called ‘merely human,’ strivings and passions. Even in connexion with history, they speak of Providence and the plan of Providence, and express a faith in a higher power, their ideas remain empty because they expressly declare that for them the plan of Providence is inscrutable and incomprehensible.”³³
The superior ruling classes are mortally opposed to the inferior ruling classes because these latter expressly declare that “the plan of Providence is inscrutable and incomprehensible,” namely because their own “ideas remain empty,” — for the inferior ruling classes, “mind has remained an empty word, and history a superficial play of casual, so–called ‘merely human,’ strivings and passions.” Wherefore?
“These principalities, therefore, are secure and happy. But as they are upheld by higher causes, which the human mind cannot attain to, I will abstain from speaking of them; for being exalted and maintained by God, it would be the work of a presumptuous and foolish man to discuss them … [Rulers] cannot observe all those things which are considered good in men, being often obliged, in order to maintain the state, to act against faith, against charity, against humanity, and against religion … [Rulers] must have a mind disposed to adapt itself according to the wind, and as the variations of fortune dictate, and, as I said before, not deviate from what is good, if possible, but be able to do evil if necessitated … It is not unknown to me how many have been and are of opinion that worldly events are so governed by fortune and by God, that men cannot by their prudence change them, and that on the contrary there is no remedy whatever, and for this they may judge it to be useless to toil much about them, but let things be ruled by chance … Our freewill may not be altogether extinguished, I think it may be true that fortune is the ruler of half our actions, but that she allows the other half or a little less to be governed by us. I would compare her to an impetuous river that, when turbulent, inundates the plains, ruins trees and buildings, removes earth from this side and places it on the other; every one flies before it, and everything yields to its fury without being able to oppose it; and yet though it is of such a kind, still when it is quiet, men can make provision against it by dams and banks, so that when it rises it will either go into a canal or its rush will not be so wild and dangerous. It happens similarly with fortune, which shows her power where no measures have been taken to resist her, and turns her fury where she knows that no dams or barriers have been made to hold her … if one could change one’s nature with time and circumstances, fortune would never change … fortune is a woman, and it is necessary, if you wish to master her, to conquer her by force; and it can be seen that she lets herself be overcome by these rather than by those who proceed coldly. And therefore, like a woman, she is a friend to the young, because they are less cautious, fiercer, and master her with greater audacity … God will not do everything, in order not to deprive us of freewill.”³⁴
Why are the superior ruling classes mortally opposed to inferior ruling classes in world history? The superior ruling classes do not expressly declare that “the plan of Providence is inscrutable and incomprehensible,” namely, because their own ideas do not remain empty, — for the superior ruling classes, on the other hand, mind is not an empty word, and history is not a superficial play of casual, so–called “merely human,” strivings and passions. Wherefore? World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind, and some of them are directly at one with that deed and it is not concealed from them, as their aim and object, — as the historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life in world history: The superior ruling classes, in contradistinction to the inferior ruling classes, are not therefore absorbed in their mundane interests, and are therefore all the time the conscious tools and organs of the world mind.
What therefore is the world historical nature of the inferior ruling classes, according to the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism? All actions, says the Pure Hegel, including world historical actions, culminate with individuals as subjects giving actuality to the substantial, namely, while the consciousness of civilizations is absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind: World historical individuals and actions are the living instruments of what is in substance the deed of the world mind and they are therefore directly at one with that deed and it is concealed from them and is not their aim and object. The decline and fall of civilizations signalizes the emergence of a higher principle as the pure negative of its own. When this happens, mind passes over into the new principle and so marks out another civilization for world historical significance.
The historical development of the principle of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life is in substance the deed of the world mind, namely, as individual subjects giving actuality to the substantial, from the embryonic stage until it blossoms: While they are absorbed in their mundane interests, they are all the time the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind. They are the inferior ruling classes. Mind passes over into the new principle and so marks out another civilization for world historical significance:
“The declining nation has lost the interest of the absolute; it may indeed absorb the higher principle positively and begin building its life on it, but the principle is only like an adopted child, not like a relative to whom its ties are immanently vital and vigorous. Perhaps it loses its autonomy, or it may still exist, or drag out its existence, as a particular state or a group of states and involve itself without rhyme or reason in manifold enterprises at home and battles abroad.”³⁵
What is the world historical nature of the inferior ruling classes of declining civilizations? They are “without rights, and they, along with those whose hour has struck already, count no longer in world history.”³⁶ There is no longer any interest between the inferior ruling classes and the absolute in world history, because the collapse of civilization means the loss of “interest” between the absolute and the inferior ruling classes:
“If it is asked why then, since 1850 at any rate, his [Hegel’s] writings have been a good deal neglected, the answer is not difficult to give. It is only by the multitude that they have been laid aside. The principle has penetrated in this country into the attitude and methods of some of the later thinkers who have been amongst us, men like Green, Caird, Bradley and Bosanquet. These have indeed hardly been Hegelians. It was not probable that a system which was given to the world a century since should serve the world sufficiently today. But its broad principle has profoundly moved the English thinkers to whom I have referred, and I might add instances of the same kind from the United States and from other countries, as well as from Germany … We need not be deterred by the feeling that we are no longer interested in the doctrine of the Absolute which engrossed attention in the early part of the last century.”³⁷
The Pure Hegel is therefore the modern Western philosophical progenitor of the life and death struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes in world history:
“If states disagree and their particular wills cannot be harmonized, the matter can only be settled by war … It is as particular entities that states enter into relations with one another. Hence their relations are on the largest scale a maelstrom of external contingency and the inner particularity of passions, private interests and selfish ends, abilities and virtues, vices, force, and wrong.”³⁸
While the struggle between ruling classes is the arena of external contingency, wherein is found, “the unconscious tools and organs of the world mind,” and although, “the principles of the national minds are wholly restricted on account of their particularity, for it is in this particularity that, as existent individuals, they have their objective actuality and their self–consciousness,” nevertheless:
“Their deeds and destinies in their reciprocal relations to one another are the dialectic of the finitude [die erscheinende Dialektik der Endlichkeit] of these minds, and out of it arises the universal mind, the mind of the world, free from all restriction, producing itself as that which exercises its right — and its right is the highest right of all — over these finite minds in the ‘history of the world which is the world’s court of judgement.’”³⁹
From out of the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes, namely the dialectic of finitude, arises the universal mind, the mind of the world, free from all restriction: The dialectic of world history, as the dialectic of finitude, is the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes, and is the principle of the historical development of the self–conscious freedom of ethical life, and therefore according to the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism, the advancement of the self–developing self–consciousness of the world mind in the aggrandizement of Western civilization: Globalism is therefore the supremacy of the superior ruling class (das Herrschende).
As the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelianism has foretold, the grandeur and decadence of Western civilization is the result of the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes, as the dialectic of finitude: The aggrandizement of Western civilization is the work of superior ruling classes, while the decline of civilization is the work of inferior ruling classes. The rise of Western civilization in world history is therefore the result of superior ruling classes, whether aristocratic, monarchical or democratic.
Thus, the struggle between ruling classes and the birth of world civilization (Herrlichkeit) is the dialectic of world history in the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelism. But which Hegel is the Hegel of the modern sophists?
“The will of the great man performs the essential function of the sovereign will: It brings into being the law which determines the activity of every power within the State, not only that of the government, but that of the legislature and that of the monarch himself. But it is not a sovereign will precisely because it lies outside the State which it constitutes. The task of the great men is ended when the State which they wrought unconsciously to achieve is completely realized. Hegel’s State itself fails to be sovereign in the full and proper sense by lacking an organ to give expression to this will.”⁴⁰
Pray tell, where exactly is it in the Pure Hegel that the will of the great rulers who perform the essential function of the sovereign will, “is ended when the State they wrought unconsciously to achieve is completely realized”? Where is it exactly in the Pure Hegel that the “State itself fails to be sovereign in the full and proper sense by lacking an organ to give expression to this will”? From whence comes the pseudo–Hegel of modern irrationalism? The answer is readily available: In the writings and publications of Ludwig Boumann, Friedrich Christoph Förster, Eduard Gans, Karl Ritter von Hegel, Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Philipp Konrad Marheinecke, Carl Ludwig Michelet, Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz and Johannes Karl Hartwig Schulze (Schultze), namely, from the works of impure Hegelianism is found the pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism of modern irrationalism:
“It may indeed be disconcerting that only today do we doubt — and not everyone does — that Hegel’s lectures … are actually reproduced authentically in the published edition … that did not become full–blown for more than a hundred and fifty years. We can hardly examine here all the reasons for this circumstance.”⁴¹
In other words, Hegel is rejected as a sophist and anti–democrat by modern irrationalists in virtue of material drawn from the works of impure Hegelianism. Modern sophists ignore and neglect the rational distinction between the genuine Hegel and Pure Hegelism of the originalausgabe on the one hand, and the pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism of their own impure Hegelianism on the other hand:
“Hegel’s own course notes and those of his students should be used with caution to clarify and illustrate the meaning of the texts he published during his lifetime … In general, the student notes written during or after Hegel’s classes should be used with caution … What has been said about the student notes must also be applied to the so–called Zusatze (additions), added by ‘the friends’ to the third edition of the Encyclopedia (1830) and the book on Rechtsphilosophie … Some commentators, however, seem to prefer the Zusatze over Hegel’s own writings; additions are sometimes even quoted as the only textual evidence for the interpretation of highly controversial issues. For scholarly use, however, we should use them only as applications, confirmations, or concretizations of Hegel’s theory. Only in cases where authentic texts are unavailable may they be accepted as indications of Hegel’s answers to questions that are not treated in his handwritten or published work. If they contradict the explicit theory of the authorized texts, we can presume that the student is wrong, unless we can show that it is plausible that they express a change in the evolution of Hegel’s thought … According to Leopold von Henning’s preface (pp. vi–vii) in his edition (1839) of the Encyclopädie of 1830, the editors of the Encyclopedia sometimes changed or completed the sentences in which the students had rendered Hegel’s classes.”⁴²
Thus, modern irrationalism and impure Hegelianism, namely, pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism, ignores and neglects the dialectic of finitude (die erscheinende Dialektik der Endlichkeit) as the struggle between superior and inferior ruling classes, and the rise of world civilization as the supremacy of Global rational political and economic order in universal history:
“The concrete Ideas, the minds of the nations, have their truth and their destiny in the concrete Idea which is absolute universality, i.e., in the world mind. Around its throne they stand as the executors of its actualization and as signs and ornaments of its grandeur [Herrlichkeit]. As mind, it is nothing but its active movement towards absolute knowledge of itself and therefore towards freeing its consciousness from the form of natural immediacy and so coming to itself.”⁴³
Modern irrationalism is therefore the weapon of the inferior ruling class, namely, modern European raison d’État: “The outlook of Kant’s philosophy is a high one … the march of God in the world, that is what the state is.”⁴⁴ The irrationalists therefore mean by the “noologism” and the “rationalistic temper” of Plato and Hegel (namely, the opposition of Western Idealism to modern sophistry), that reason is the weapon of the superior ruling class, albeit rechristened by the sophists as “unreason,” which they wrongly foist upon Western philosophy. In the eyes of modern irrationalism, Western philosophy is sophistry. Hegel is thus sophistically identified with Plato, and both are then made into anti–democrats (totalitarians), as the congenital enemies of what the modern sophists name rational political and economic order.
What exactly the sophists mean by modern democracy or rational political and economic order (so–called liberalism, republicanism, nationalism, socialism and communism) is spelled out in the world of today as criticism, empiricism and even science in the backwards, outdated and corrupt political economy of modernity (in contradistinction to their pejorative usage of such terms as dogmatism, idealism and metaphysics).⁴⁵ Their sophistical political economy is therefore culled from the modern subjectivism, relativism and irrationalism of Locke,⁴⁶ Leibniz, Hume and Kant: As the Machiavellism of the Napoléonic and French revolutionary conception of right, which is not the rational conception of right found in the Magna Carta and the Constitution of the United States of America. ⁴⁷
The political and economic doctrine of Locke’s version of so–called constitutional, as opposed to absolute, monarchy is forged in the modern European warfare between Gallicanism and Ultramontanism (unleashed by Luther and the revolt of Protestantism), and especially the revolutionary struggle between William of Orange and King James II: This struggle also involves the late mediaeval theological distinction between Catholicism and Protestantism in the political and economic clash between the old and new world historical forms of Christendom, — as the moment of the modern self–determination of the self–comprehending pure notion, namely, as the rise of Globalism:
“Admirers of Hegel are accustomed to refer to the first edition [Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline], as having most of the author’s freshness and power … in America, no one can look back a few years, without observing that the whole tone of our public men has changed, and that the phrases, ‘progress,’ ‘necessary development,’ and ‘God in history,’ occur with marked frequency.”⁴⁸
In the first editions of the great works of Hegel’s lifetime, the Owl of Minerva is successively released from the coils of modern irrationalism: Pure Hegelianism is the sublation of modernity that ends the mental struggle between reason and unreason in world history. Pure Hegelianism reconciles the strife between Descartes, Spinoza and Berkeley on the one side, and Locke, Leibniz and Hume on the other, in the struggle between Kant and Hegel in 20th century world history: Americanism is therefore the concrete sublation of Pure Hegelianism.⁴⁹
World civilization is therefore Globalism, the rational foundation of which is therefore the developmental unification of the coaxial integration of the American world.
ENDNOTES
THE NEW HEGELIAN ORTHODOXY
1. Hegel, “Die Verfassung Deutschlands (1801–1802),” Sämtliche Werke: Schriften zur Politik und Rechtsphilosophie, Unter Mitwirkung von Dr. Otto Weiß, Hrsg., Georg Lasson, Band VII, Leipzig, 1913, 113: “Hier kann aber von keiner Wahl der Mittel die Rede [sein], brandige Glieder können nicht mit Lavendelwasser geheilt werden.”
2. Hegel, “Introduction: General Division of Logic,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator & John Niemeyer Findlay, forward, New York, 1976, 62. [1969]: “I would mention that in this work I frequently refer to the Kantian philosophy (which to many may seem superfluous) because whatever may be said, both in this work and elsewhere, about the precise character of this philosophy and about particular parts of its exposition, it constitutes the base and the starting–point of recent German philosophy and this its merit remains unaffected by whatever faults may be found in it. The reason, too, why reference must often be made to it in the objective logic is that it enters into detailed consideration of important, more specific aspects of logic, whereas later philosophical works have paid little attention to these and in some instances have only displayed a crude — not unavenged — contempt for them. The [62] philosophizing which is most widespread among us does not go beyond the Kantian results, that Reason cannot acquire knowledge of any true content or subject matter and in regard to absolute truth must be directed by faith. But what with Kant is a result, forms the immediate starting–point in this philosophizing, so that the preceding exposition from which that result issued and which is a philosophical cognition, is cut away beforehand. The Kantian philosophy thus serves as a cushion for intellectual indolence which soothes itself with the conviction that everything is already proved and settled. Consequently for genuine knowledge, for a specific content of thought which is not to be found in such barren and arid complacency, one must turn to that preceding exposition.”
See also: “In this work [Science of Logic] I make frequent references to the Kantian philosophy (which to many might seem superfluous) because, whatever might be said here or elsewhere of its distinctive character or of particular parts of its exposition, it constitutes the foundation and the starting point of the new German philosophy, and this is a merit of which it can boast undiminished by whatever fault may be found in it. An added reason for these frequent references in the objective logic is that Kantian philosophy delves deeply into important, more specific aspects of the logic, whereas later philosophical expositions have paid little attention to these aspects and in some instances have even expressed crude — though not unavenged — contempt for them. The philosophizing most widespread among us does not reach past the Kantian results that reason cannot cognize any true content, and that, when it comes to absolute truth, it must be directed to faith. But what for Kant is the result is for this philosophizing the immediate starting point, so that the exposition which precedes the result, from which this result is derived and which constitutes [the Kantian theory of] philosophical cognition, is excised beforehand. The philosophy of Kant thus serves as a cushion for an intellectual indolence which takes comfort in the fact that everything is already proved and settled. For cognition and a specific content of thought which is not found in such a barren and arid complacency, one must therefore turn to that preceding exposition.”
Hegel, “Introduction: General Division of the Logic,” The Science of Logic,George Di Giovanni, editor and translator, Michael Baur, General editor, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2010, 38–43; 40.
See: Hegel, “Einleitung: Allgemeine Eintheilung der Logik,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Zweite Ausgabe, Stuttgart und Tübingen, 1832, 26–34; 29–30. [1812]
See also: Hegel, “Einleitung,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Nürnberg, 1812, i–xxvii.
Remark: According to Hegel, the only merit of the Kantian philosophy (𝔡𝔦𝔢 𝔎𝔞𝔫𝔱𝔦𝔰𝔠𝔥𝔢 𝔓𝔥𝔦𝔩𝔬𝔰𝔬𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔢) is that Kantianism is popular and influential in Germany: Kant’s philosophy has merit, according to Hegel, as a passing–phase of world history. Hegel therefore refers to the Kantian philosophy in the Science of Logic because he discusses important questions of logic, which he opposes to the transcendental logic of Kant. Kantian results (𝔡𝔢𝔫 𝔎𝔞𝔫𝔱𝔦𝔰𝔠𝔥𝔢𝔫 ℜ𝔢𝔰𝔲𝔩𝔱𝔞𝔱𝔢𝔫), which in Kant’s eyes are proved, lead to skepticism of the absolute truth, — which he likewise considers as demonstrated by his theory of 𝔗𝔯𝔞𝔫𝔰𝔷𝔢𝔫𝔡𝔢𝔫𝔱𝔞𝔩𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔩𝔬𝔰𝔬𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔢. Kantian philosophy ignores such niceties and merely takes Kant’s skepticism for granted without any inquiry: The epigones ignore their precise affiliation to Kant’s theories. The skeptical meaning of Kantian theory must be found in Kant’s work, not in his epigones, who use Kantianism as an excuse for their mental flabbiness (intellectual indolence). In other words, the Kantian philosophy of Hegel’s time is sophistry (intellectual indolence and barren and arid complacency). Hegel complains that it is difficult to argue with Kantian sophists who are ignorant of Kant’s arguments: “The exposition which precedes the [Kantian] result … is excised beforehand.” Once Hegel’s enemies are uncovered as Kantians, the refutation of their sophistry comes easily: “[Their] result is derived and … [the exposition] constitutes [Kant’s theory of] philosophical cognition.” Thus, in returning to the roots of Kant’s exposition, the epigones will discover they are surpassed in world history: In the eyes of the genuine Hegel, the meaning of whose statements are not corrupted by impure Hegelianism, those Kantian philosophers who refuse to recognize that their time is come, they are become modern sophists.
Hegel discusses 𝔱𝔯𝔞𝔫𝔰𝔷𝔢𝔫𝔡𝔢𝔫𝔱𝔞𝔩𝔢 𝔏𝔬𝔤𝔦𝔨 in the Science of Logic, not to bring the Copernican Revolution to fruition, but in order to refute Kant’s 𝔗𝔯𝔞𝔫𝔰𝔷𝔢𝔫𝔡𝔢𝔫𝔱𝔞𝔩𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔩𝔬𝔰𝔬𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔢 and the 𝔎𝔞𝔫𝔱𝔦𝔰𝔠𝔥𝔢 𝔓𝔥𝔦𝔩𝔬𝔰𝔬𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔢:
“In connection with the refutation of a philosophical system, I have also remarked quite in general that we must get over the distorted idea that that system has to be represented as if thoroughly false, and as if the true system stood to the false as only opposed to it … Refutation would have to come not from outside, that is, not proceed from assumptions lying outside the system and irrelevant to it. The system need only refuse to recognize those assumptions; the defect is such only for one who starts from such needs and requirements as are based on them … The nerve, therefore, of any external refutation consists solely in obstinately clinging to the opposite categories of these assumptions, for example, to the absolute self–subsistence of the thinking individual as against the form of thought which in the absolute substance is posited as identical with extension. Effective refutation must infiltrate the opponent’s stronghold and meet him on his own ground; there is no point in attacking him outside his territory and claiming jurisdiction where he is not.”
Hegel, “The Science of Subjective Logic or the Doctrine of the Concept: Of the Concept in General,” The Science of Logic, George Di Giovanni, editor and translator, introduction, Michael Baur, general editor, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2010, 507–753 & 508–527; 511–512–512.
Hegel infiltrates Kant’s stronghold and meets him on his own ground: Genuine Hegelianism is the bona fide refutation of 𝔗𝔯𝔞𝔫𝔰𝔷𝔢𝔫𝔡𝔢𝔫𝔱𝔞𝔩𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔩𝔬𝔰𝔬𝔭𝔥𝔦𝔢, the anti–Copernican Revolution.
See: “On the 7th of November, 1831, Hegel finished the preface to a second edition of his Logic. In closing he recalled the legend that Plato revised the Republic seven times, and remarked that, despite this illustrious example, ‘the writer must content himself with what he has been allowed to achieve under the pressure of circumstances, the unavoidable waste caused by the extent and many–sidedness of the interests of the time, and the haunting doubt whether, amid the loud clamor of the day and the deafening babble of opinion … there is left any room for sympathy with the passionless stillness of a science of pure thought.’ Seven days later he died of cholera, and was buried, as he had wished, between Fichte and Solger.”
Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, “Biographical Note: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, 1770–1831,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Chicago, 1960, v–vi.
3. Eduard Gans, “Additions to The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, Chicago, 1960, Addition 86 = §135/129–Addition 152 = §258/141.
See: Eduard Gans, “Zusätze aus Hegels Vorlesungen, zusammengestellt,” Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Eduard Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, neu hrsg., von Georg Lasson, Herausgegeber, Leipzig, 1911, Zusätze 86 = §135, 318–Zusätze 152 = §258, 349: “Den Standpunkt der Kantischen Philosophie hervorhoben … Es ist der Gang Gottes in der Welt, daß der Staat ist.”
See: “From the Kantian system and its highest completion I expect a revolution in Germany. It will proceed from principles that are present and that only need to be elaborated generally and applied to all hitherto existing knowledge.”
Hegel in Clark Butler & Christiana Seiler, editors and translators, Hegel: The Letters, Bloomington, Indiana, 1984, 35.
See: “Because of his continuing support for reform [Bonapartism] after the revolutions of 1830, his lectures were banned and he was dismissed.”
John W. Burbidge, “Eduard Gans (1798–1839),” Historical Dictionary of Hegelian Philosophy, Lanham, Maryland, 2008, 80.
4. See: “The Meiner Verlag series of Hegel Vorlesungen, commencing in 1983, includes volumes that remedy drawbacks of the Werke volumes on these lectures–only topics; they distinguish the lecture series on the same topics in different years, so that there is now a more faithful representation available of what Hegel himself actually said in a given series, and how his thought, albeit not finalized, had developed or changed over time … one can see from them [the Lecture Transcripts] what Hegel actually said in a given series.”
Robert F. Brown, editor and translator, “Editorial Introduction: 1. Background Issues,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures (Together with an Introduction by Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert), Oxford, 2014, 1.
See also: “The transcripts known today for all the Berlin lecture series are consistently, even surprisingly, reliable testimonies … It may indeed be disconcerting that only today do we doubt — and not everyone does — that Hegel’s lectures … are actually reproduced authentically in the published edition … that did not become full–blown for more than a hundred and fifty years. We can hardly examine here all the reasons for this circumstance.”
Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, “Introduction: The Shape and Influence of Hegel’s Aesthetics,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures, Robert F. Brown, editor and translator, Oxford, 2014, 7–176; 32–36–36–36.
See finally: “After Hegel’s death, his former students came together with the rather noble thought of assembling various transcripts of the lecture series he gave and to which they had access, hoping to bring to the light of a general public the “system” that [they?] were convinced was completed for years and presented orally in the lecture hall. However, the methodologies through which they assembled these transcripts into standalone monographs, with the aid of Hegel’s own manuscripts for his lectures, is dubious at best. They paid little to no attention to changes between different lecture courses, combining them as they saw fit to guarantee the logical progression of the dialectical movement as they interpreted it. But without the original source material, it was impossible to test the suspicion that they may have falsified Hegel’s own views. Indeed, it was all we had to go on to have any understanding of his views. Now, however, many manuscripts and transcripts — even ones not available to his students — have been found. When one compares these manuscripts and transcripts with the lectures published by his students, the differences between them are in no case simply philological niceties … this information may drastically challenge our historical picture of Hegel.”
Sean J. McGrath and Joseph Carew, editors, “Introduction: What Remains of German Idealism?” Rethinking German Idealism, Joseph Carew, Wes Furlotte, Jean–Christophe Goddard, Adrian Johnston, Cem Kömürcü, Sean J. McGrath, Constantin Rauer, Alexander Schnell, F. Scott Scribner, Devin Zane Shaw, Konrad Utz, Jason M. Wirth, contributors, London, Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, 1–19; 4.
5. See: “The year 1992 poses a critical moral and cultural challenge for the more privileged sectors of the world–dominant societies. The challenge is heightened by the fact that within these societies, notably the first European colony liberated from imperial rule, popular struggle over many centuries has achieved a large measure of freedom, opening many opportunities for independent thought and committed action. How this challenge is addressed in the years to come will have fateful consequences. October 11, 1992 brings to an end the 500th year of the Old World Order, sometimes called the Colombian era of world history, or the Vasco da Gama era, depending on which adventurers bent on plunder got there first. Or ‘the 500–year Reich,’ to borrow the title of a commemorative volume that compares the methods and ideology of the Nazis with those of the European invaders who subjugated most of the world. The major theme of this Old World Order was a confrontation between the conquerors and the conquered on a global scale. It has taken various forms, and been given different names: Imperialism, neocolonialism, the North–South conflict, core versus periphery, G–7 (the 7 leading state capitalist industrial societies) and their satellites versus the rest. Or, more simply, Europe’s conquest of the world … ‘Hegel discoursed authoritatively on the same topics in his lectures on philosophy of history, brimming with confidence as we approach the final ‘phase of World–History,’ when Spirit reaches ‘its full maturity and strength’ in ‘the German world.’ Speaking from that lofty peak, he relates that native America was ‘physically and psychically powerless,’ its culture so limited that it ‘must expire as soon as Spirit approached it.’ Hence ‘the aborigines …gradually vanished at the breath of European activity.’ ‘A mild and passionless disposition, want of spirit, and a crouching submissiveness … are the chief characteristics of the native Americans,’ so ‘slothful’ that, under the kind ‘authority of the Friars,’ ‘at midnight a bell had to remind them even of their matrimonial duties.’ They were inferior even to the Negro, ‘the natural man in his completely wild and untamed state,’ who is beyond any ‘thought of reverence and morality ―all that we call feeling’; there is ‘nothing harmonious with humanity … in this type of character.’ ‘Among the Negroes moral sentiments are quite weak, or more strictly speaking non–existent.’ ‘Parents sell their children, and conversely children their parents, as either has the opportunity,’ and ‘The polygamy of the Negroes has frequently for its object the having many children, to be sold, every one of them, into slavery.’ Creatures at the level of ‘a mere Thing — an object of no value,’ they treat ‘as enemies’ those who seek to abolish slavery, which has ‘been the occasion of the increase of human feeling among the Negroes,’ enabling them to become ‘participant in a higher morality and the culture connected with it’ … Hegel, Philosophy, 108–9, 81–2, 93–6; ‘the German world’ presumably takes in Northwest Europe … Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. The Philosophy of History (Dover, 1956; Lectures of 1830–31).”
Noam Chomsky, Year 501: The Conquest Continues, Montréal/New York, 1993, 3–4–5–291–313.
See also: “Hegel discoursed authoritatively … in his lectures on philosophy of history.”
Chomsky, Ibidem, 4.
See finally: “Hegel’s own course notes and those of his students should be used with caution to clarify and illustrate the meaning of the texts he published during his lifetime … In general, the student notes written during or after Hegel’s classes should be used with caution … What has been said about the student notes must also be applied to the so–called Zusatze (additions), added by ‘the friends’ to the third edition of the Encyclopedia (1830) and the book on Rechtsphilosophie … Some commentators, however, seem to prefer the Zusatze over Hegel’s own writings; additions are sometimes even quoted as the only textual evidence for the interpretation of highly controversial issues. For scholarly use, however, we should use them only as applications, confirmations, or concretizations of Hegel’s theory. Only in cases where authentic texts are unavailable may they be accepted as indications of Hegel’s answers to questions that are not treated in his handwritten or published work. If they contradict the explicit theory of the authorized texts, we can presume that the student is wrong, unless we can show that it is plausible that they express a change in the evolution of Hegel’s thought … According to Leopold von Henning’s preface (pp. vi–vii) in his edition (1839) of the Encyclopädie of 1830, the editors of the Encyclopedia sometimes changed or completed the sentences in which the students had rendered Hegel’s classes.”
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy, Dordrecht, 2001, xvi–27–28–29–29.
See: Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse―Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Erste Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, Berlin, 1840, v–viii.
See also: Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse―Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Zweite Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, Berlin, 1843, v–viii.
Genuine Hegelianism, the true Gospel of Hegel which greatly influenced America over the years, especially in the Civil War, unlike impure Hegelianism, suspends judgement on matters where Hegel left us without any authorized treatise, because the speculative logical and dialectical system of the pure Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism comes only from the originalausgabe.
On issues where Hegel left us without any authorized treatise we must use the surviving course notes as the only possible access to Hegel’s thought, while the ultimate criteria for their authenticity lie in the principles of his authorized work (Adriaan Peperzak): Refutations of Hegel’s philosophy which contain as premises statements from the non–authorized work are not inferentially equivalent with arguments which contain as premises statements from Hegel’s authorized work because the former involve only the “possible access” to Hegel’s thought. The authenticity and “possible access” of such statements as premises lies in their reconciliation to the principles of the originalausgabe. But the interpretative determination, the hermeneutical judgement that entails the semantic reconciliation, that makes these non–authorized statements “authentic,” and therefore acceptable as premises in arguments against Hegel, does not thereby make them inferentially equivalent to the statements from the originalausgabe: They involve only the “possible access” to Hegel’s thought, whereas the latter involve the actual access to Hegel’s thought. In other words, the difference here between interpretative possibility and actuality entails the distinction between weaker and stronger levels of inference in the demonstrability of the refutation: A strong refutation of Hegel’s philosophy therefore contains premises from the originalausgabe, whereas a weak refutation of Hegel’s philosophy contains premises from the originalausgabe and from the non–authorized work, while a sophistical refutation contains no premise from the originalausgabe. Refutation of the Hegelian philosophy is inseparable from Hegel philology: Therefore, dialectical inference is inseparable from dialectical hermeneutics, as the notion of dialectical scientivity,―as the speculative logical and dialectical system of the pure Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism.
6. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope, London, 1999, 71.
7. See: “Gradually, Kant and Hegel conquered the universities of France and England … [Hegel’s] system could never have arisen if Kant’s had not existed.”
Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy and its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day, London, 1947, 748–757.
8. Johann Eduard Erdmann, A History of Philosophy: German Philosophy Since Hegel, 4th German edition, vol. 3, London, 1899, 66–81.
9. See: “We [American] irrationalists do not foam at the mouth and behave like animals … we Americans have been more consistent than the Europeans.” Richard Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope, London, 1999, xix–xx.
10. See: “Come it will, and when ye hear a crashing such as never before has been heard in the world’s history, then know that at last the German thunderbolt has fallen. At this commotion the eagles will drop dead from the skies and the lions in the farthest wastes of Africa will bite their tails and creep into their royal lairs. There will be played in Germany a drama compared to which the French Revolution will seem but an innocent idyll. At present, it is true, everything is tolerably quiet; and though here and there some few men create a little stir, do not imagine these are to be the real actors in the piece. They are only little curs chasing one another round the empty arena, barking and snapping at one another, till the appointed hour when the troop of gladiators appear to fight for life and death. And the hour will come. As on the steps of an empty amphitheater, the nations will group themselves around Germany to witness the terrible combat.”
Heinrich Heine, Religion and Philosophy in Germany: A Fragment, Boston, 1959, xiv. [1834]
11. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, New Edition, 2 vols., New York, 1824, I/381–II/203. [1690]
See: “Locke was heavily involved in the slave trade, both through his investments and through his administrative supervision of England’s burgeoning colonial activities … The attempt to reconcile Locke’s involvement in the slave trade with his reputation as a philosopher of liberal freedom has a long history, beginning shortly after the abolition of the slave trade … Locke’s readers are faced with the problem of how he could have been so intimately involved in promoting an activity that he apparently knew to be unjustified … We are disturbed by the ease with which some commentators excuse Locke of racism or minimize its significance … to advocate, administer, and profit from a specifically racialized form of slavery is clear evidence of [Locke’s] racism, if the word is to have any meaning at all.”
Robert Bernasconi and Anika Maaza Mann, “The Contradictions of Racism: Locke, Slavery, and the Two Treatises,” Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy, Andrew Valls, editor, Ithaca/London, 2005, 89–89–90–91–91.
12. See Cartesius: “Ego cogito, ergo sum, sive existo … ea enim est natura nostrae mentis, ut generales propostiones ex particularium cognitione efformet.”
Cartesius, “Secundæ Responsiones,” Œuvres de Descartes: Meditationes de Prima Philosophia, vol. 7, Charles Adam & Paul Tannery, éditeurs, Paris, 1904, 140–141.
How very clear and distinct are the ideas of Cartesius, coming from his very own hand, although his best translators are also clear and distinct, but less clear and less distinct than the very words of Cartesius himself, as found in his very greatest works, since his Latin is now a dead language, while his modern interpreters fail to elucidate the rational foundations of their sophistical critiques.
13. Joseph Stalin, “Anarchism or Socialism?” Works: 1901–1907, vol. 1, Moscow, 1954, 307–321.
See: Stalin, “Anarchism or Socialism?” Nobati, Musha, Akhali Tskhovreba, June–July 1906, 1–4.
See: “Rational idealism is profound knowledge of the unknowable.” [Reinster Idealismus deckt sich unbewußt mit tiefster Erkenntnis]
Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf, 851–855 auflage, München, 1943, 328.
See finally: “It is now known that unlike Kant, Hegel was despised by the Nazis.”
Yitzhak Y. Melamed and Peter Thielke, “Hegelianism,” New Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Game Theory to Lysenkoism, vol. 3, Maryanne Cline Horowitz, editor in chief, New York, 2005, 977.
14. From the London School of Economics and Political Science in Bertrand Russell, German Social Democracy: Six Lectures, London and New York, 1896, 2–163.
See also: “Marx is at once logically a dialectical rationalist and metaphysically a dogmatic materialist.”
Russell, Ibidem, 5.
Bertrand Russell’s sophistical (British Kantio–Hegelian) conceptions of logic and metaphysics cause him to completely neglect or ignore the “critical and revolutionary” (Kantian) nature of Marx’s “rational” dialectic.
See finally: “No logical absurdity results from the hypothesis that the world consists of myself and my thoughts and feelings and sensations, and that everything else is mere fancy … Philosophy is to be studied, not for the sake of any definite answers to its questions, since no definite answers can, as a rule, be known to be true.”
Russell, The Problems of Philosophy, London, 1912, 34–249.
15. Karl Marx in Bertrand Russell, German Social Democracy: Six Lectures, London and New York, 1896, 4–5.
See: “In its mystified form, [the Hegelian] dialectic became the fashion in Germany … In its rational form it [the Hegelian Dialectic] is a scandal and an abomination to bourgeoisdom.”
Karl Marx, Ibidem, 5.
See also: “[Feuerbach] says that his present teaching, so far from being an unfolding of Hegelian theories, on the contrary originated in opposition to these theories. If any one is to be called his forerunner, let it be Schleiermacher … he afterwards said that the so-called Right Wing of the Hegelian school was the one which was in complete harmony with the master.”
Erdmann, Ibidem, 79.
16. Alexander Herzen, Selected Philosophical Works, Moscow, 1956, 521.
See: “An Absolute Idea, is a theological invention of the idealist Hegel … the ordinary human idea became divine with Hegel when it was divorced from man and man’s brain … Hegel’s ‘Absolute Idea’ gathered together all the contradictions of Kantian idealism.”
Lenin, Collected Works: Materialism and Empirio–Criticism, 1908, vol. 14, Moscow, 1977, 227–232. [1962]
17. See: “Kant was a turning point in the history of Western philosophy because he was a reductio ad absurdum of the attempt to distinguish between the role of the subject and the role of the object in constituting knowledge … Hegel himself used the terms ‘subjective’ and ‘objective’ … and used the term ‘union of subject and object’ to describe the end of history. This was a mistake.”
Richard Rorty, Philosophy and Social Hope, London, 1999, 49.
18. Saul Kripke, “Naming and Necessity,” Semantics of Natural Language, Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, editors, Dordrecht, 1972, 288–289.
See: “Surely there was no logical fate hanging over either Aristotle or Hitler which made it in any sense inevitable that they should have possessed the properties we regard as important to them.”
Kripke, Ibidem, 289.
See also: “[Hitler] was one of the most evil men in world history.”
William Alexander Jenks, “Adolf Hitler,” The World Book Encyclopedia, vol. 9, Chicago, 1971, 236.
See: Jenks, Vienna and the Young Hitler, New York, 1960.
19. Hegel, “Einleitung,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objective Logik, erster Band, Nürnberg, 1812, xiii.
20. See: “We cannot obey these murderers [Kennedy Administration]. They are abominable. They are the wickedest people who ever lived in the history of man and it is our duty to do what we can against them.”
Bertrand Russell (1 April 1961) in Harvey Arthur DeWeerd, Lord Russell’s War Crimes Tribunal, Santa Monica, 1967, 3.
21. Bertrand Russell (1963) in Harvey Arthur DeWeerd, Lord Russell’s War Crimes Tribunal, Santa Monica, 1967, 4.
22. Hegel, Great Books of the Western World: The Philosophy of Right, vol. 46, Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor, Chicago, 1960, §352, 112.
23. Sidney Hook, Reason, Social Myths, and Democracy, New York, 1940, 76–105.
See: “The social principles of Christianity in so far as they are specifically Christian and construed in terms of the institutional behaviour of churches can never be adequate to profound social change.”
Sidney Hook, “Is Marxism Compatible with Christianity?” Christianity and Marxism: A Symposium, S.L. Solon, editor, New York, 1934, 31.
See also: Bertrand Russell, Why I Am Not a Christian: And Other Essays on Religion and Related Subjects, London, 1957.
24. Noam Chomsky, “Interview Transcript,” from YouTube, 2015–2016.
25. Hook, Reason, Social Myths, and Democracy, 296.
26. John Dewey, “Kant and Philosophic Method,” Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 18(1 April 1884): 171–172.
See: “Kant, the founder of modernest philosophy … is the transition of the old abstract thought, the old meaningless conception of experience, into the new concrete thought, the ever growing, ever rich experience.”
Dewey, Ibidem, 162–174.
See also: John Dewey in Yervant Hovhannes Krikorian, editor, Naturalism and the Human Spirit, 1st edition, New York, 1944.
27. Hegel, Great Books of the Western World: The Philosophy of Right, 6.
28. See: “Culture and cultural identities, which at the broadest level are civilization identities, are shaping the patterns of cohesion, disintegration, and conflict in the post–Cold War world … Intellectual and scientific advance, Thomas Kuhn showed in his classic The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, consists of the displacement of one paradigm, which has become increasingly incapable of explaining new or newly discovered facts, by a new paradigm, which does account for those facts in a more satisfactory fashion.”
Samuel Phillips Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order, New York, 1996, 20–30.
29. Sidney Hook, Social Democracy and America: 1976 Convention Statement of Social Democrats, USA, New York, 1976.
30. Hegel, Ibidem, §340, 110.
31. See: “Prime Minister Brian Mulroney has promised the labor movement a major voice in shaping policies adopted by his Progressive Conservative government. In a videotaped address yesterday to the CFL convention he said labor must play ‘a full partnership role’ with business and government in deciding the country’s future.”
Anonymous, “Social Net Not Part of Trade Talks: Reisman,” The Montreal Gazette, 15 May 1986, A9.
32. See: “Jean–Louis Lévesque, the Montréal financier from far–away Gaspé, ‘knew first–hand the difficulties that awaited a French–Canadian in business, and therefore he took the young Paul Desmarais under his wing, and led him into the realm of French–Canadian high finance … The Lévesque which most Canadians have heard about is the great orator, René, the Minister of Natural Resources of the Province of Québec. Jean–Louis Lévesque is his wealthy distant cousin, who owns the largest financial empire in Québec.’”
Jules Bélanger, Jean–Louis Lévesque: La montée d’un Gaspésien aux sommets des affaires, Saint–Laurent, 1996, 138–166.
See also: “Paul Desmarais learned to always cultivate very close political and economic connexions with provincial and federal élites, so that every Premier of Québec and Prime Minister of Canada, at least since the time of Maurice Duplessis, used to eat from his hand … in the largest financial transaction in Canadian history, Paul Desmarais sold Consolidated–Bathurst, the crown jewel of the Québec pulp and paper industry, which had benefited from very generous subsidies from Québec taxpayers over the years, for $2.6 billion to American investors. The sale of the Montréal Trust later followed for some $550 million: Thus, Paul Desmarais ripped–off $3 billion in natural resources from the hard–working people of Québec … Paul Desmarais was probably the most corrupt businessman in Canadian history.”
Robin Philpot, “Paul Desmarais: un bilan s’impose,” Le Devoir, 12 octobre 2013.
See also: Philpot, Derrière l’État Desmarais: Power, 2e édition, Montréal, 2014.
33. John Fitzgerald Kennedy, “How to Prepare for the Presidency,” The World Book Encyclopedia, vol. 15, Chicago, 1971, 681.
34. Those men and women who harness the vast political and economic powers of the internet, which are embryonic in the world of today, will become the first trillionaires: Their task is the project of Global rational political and economic order … the financial, commercial and industrial foundations of the Space Age.
This brief outline is the last of what remains of a manuscript, the labor of more than a decade, which was unfortunately lost some years ago: The details of which, for the most part, have long been obliterated from the author’s memory.
CHAPTER 1: MODERN ENEMIES OF PLATO AND HEGEL
1. Edward VII in Giles St. Aubyn, Edward VII: Prince and King, New York, 1979, 431. [Italics added]
See: “Churchill was never a rational man … in moments of crisis he [Churchill] sought guidance not by reasoning but by intuition.”
William Manchester, The Last Lion: Winston Spencer Churchill: Alone, 1932–1940, Boston, 1988, 664.
2. Ernst Mach, “Author’s Preface to the Seventh German Edition,” The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development, Supplement to the Third English Edition Containing the Author’s Additions to the Seventh German Edition, Philip Edward Bertrand Jourdain, translator and annotator, Chicago and London, 1915, xi. [1912] [Italics added]
See: “With regard to the monstrous conceptions of absolute space and absolute time … Newton indeed spoke much about these things, but throughout made no serious application of them.”
Ernst Mach, Ibidem, 1915, xii. See: Ernst Mach, Die Mechanik in ihrer Enwickelung: Historisch–Kritisch Dargestellt, Siebente verbesserte und vermehrte Auflage, Leipzig, 1912.
3. David Lloyd George in Robert Kinloch Massie, Nicholas and Alexandra, New York, 1967, 459. [Italics added]
See: “Nicholas, his arm still around Alexis, began to rise from his chair to protect his wife and son. He had just time to say ‘What …?’ before Yurovsky pointed his revolver directly at the Tsar’s head and fired. Nicholas died instantly. At this signal, the entire squad of executioners began to shoot. Alexandra had time only to raise her hand and make the sign of the cross before she too was killed by a single bullet. Olga, Tatiana and Marie, standing behind her mother, were hit and died quickly. Botkin, Kharitonnov and Trupp also fell in the hail of bullets. Demidora, the maid, survived the first volley, and rather than reload, the executioners took rifles from the next room and pursued her, stabbing with bayonets. Screaming, running back and forth along the wall like a trapped animal, she tried to fend them off with a cushion. At last she fell, pierced by bayonets more than thirty times. Jimmy the spaniel was killed when his head was crushed by a rifle butt. The room, filled with the smoke and stench of gunpowder, became suddenly quiet. Blood was running in streams from the bodies on the floor. Then there was a movement and a slow groan. Alexis, lying on the floor still in the arms of the Tsar, feebly moved his hand to clutch his father’s coat. Savagely, one of the executioners kicked the Tsarevich in the head with his heavy boot. Yurovsky stepped up and fired two shots into the boy’s ear. Just at that moment, Anastasia, who had only fainted, regained consciousness and screamed. With bayonets and rifle butts, the entire band turned on her. In a moment, she too lay still.”
Robert Kinloch Massie, Nicholas and Alexandra, New York, 1967, 517.
See also: “The renovation of Parliamentary government, the transformation of the conditions of the ownership and occupation of land, the relations between the Governments at home and our adventures abroad in contact with inferior races, the limitations on free contract, and the rights of majorities to restrict the private acts of minorities, these are only some of the questions that time and circumstance are pressing upon us.”
John Morley (Lord Morley of Blackburn) in Kant’s Principles of Politics Including His Essay on Perpetual Peace: A Contribution to Political Science, William Hastie, editor & translator, Edinburgh, 1891, xxxviii–xxxix.
See also: “The Republican Constitution is, thus, the only one which arises out of the idea of the Original Compact upon which all the rightful legislation of a people is founded … the Republican Constitution is the only one which perfectly corresponds to the Rights of Man.”
Immanuel Kant in Kant’s Principles of Politics Including His Essay on Perpetual Peace: A Contribution to Political Science, William Hastie, editor & translator, Edinburgh, 1891, 89–116. [Kant, Zum ewigen Frieden, 1795]
See also: “The Republican Constitution is not to be confounded with the Democratic Constitution … of the three forms of the State, a Democracy, in the proper sense of the word, is necessarily a despotism; because it establishes an Executive power in which All resolve about, and, it may be, also against, any One who is not in accord with it; and consequently the All who thus resolve are really not all; which is a contradiction of the Universal Will with itself and with liberty.”
Immanuel Kant, Ibidem, 91–92.
See also: “The conception of a noumenon is problematical … the conception of a noumenon is therefore not the conception of an object, but merely a problematical conception … my existence cannot be considered as an inference from the proposition, ‘I think,’ as Descartes maintained.”
Immanuel Kant, “The Critique of Pure Reason,” Great Books of the Western World: Kant, John Miller Dow Meiklejohn, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, Chicago, 1960, 106–106–127.
See finally: “The concept of the noumenon is problematical … the concept of the noumenon is not therefore the concept of an object, but only a problem … the so–called syllogism of Cartesius, cogito, ergo sum, is in reality tautological.”
Immanuel Kant, Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: A Commemoration of the Centenary of Its First Publication, vol. 2, Friedrich Max Müller, translator, London, 1881, 249–250–308.
4. Ferdinand Canning Scott Schiller, Plato or Protagoras? Being a Critical Examination of the Protagoras Speech in the Theaetetus with Some Remarks Upon Error, Oxford, 1908, 29.
See: “Has not the time come when Kant’s ‘Copernican change of standpoint’ might at last be put into practice seriously, and when Truth, instead of being offered up to idols and sacrificed to ‘ideals,’ might at length be depicted in her human beauty and simplicity?”
Ferdinand Canning Scott Schiller, Studies in Humanism, London, 1907, 178.
See finally: “Plato, abandoning the world of sense because of the narrow limits it sets to the understanding, ventured upon the wings of ideas beyond it, into the void space of pure intellect. He [Plato] did not reflect that he made no real progress by all his efforts; for he met with no resistance which might serve him for support, as it were, whereon to rest, and on which he might apply his powers, in order to let the intellect acquire momentum for its progress … Plato employed the expression idea in a way that plainly showed he meant by it something which is never derived from the senses, but which far transcends even the conceptions of the understanding, inasmuch as in experience nothing perfectly corresponding to them could be found. Ideas are, according to him, archetypes of things themselves, and not merely keys to possible experiences … In his view, they flow from the highest reason, by which they have been imparted to human reason, which, however, exists no longer in its original state, but is obliged with great labour to recall by reminiscence―which is called philosophy―the old but now sadly obscured ideas. I will not here enter upon any literary investigation of the sense which this sublime philosopher attached to this expression … I cannot follow him [Plato] in this, and as little can I follow him in his mystical deduction of these ideas, or in his hypostatization of them … What I have termed an ideal was in Plato’s philosophy an idea of the divine mind―an individual object present to its pure intuition, the most perfect of every kind of possible beings, and the archetype of all phenomenal existences … Aristotle may be regarded as head of the empiricists, and Plato of the noologists.”
Immanuel Kant, “The Critique of Pure Reason,” Great Books of the Western World: Kant, vol. 42, John Miller Dow Meiklejohn, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, Chicago, 1960, 16–113–113–114–173–249.
But which Platonic “ideas” are these, drawn from the Plato of Aldus Pius Manutius and Μάρκος Μουσοῦρος, Marsilius Ficinus, Henricus Stephanus and Joannes Serranus or perhaps even from Daniel Albert Wyttenbach?
Kant: “I will not here enter upon any literary investigation of the sense which this sublime philosopher [Plato] attached to this expression [idea].”
The Kantian distinction between noologism and empiricism in the Kantian history of philosophy is therefore unfounded, otherwise mired in modern subjectivism, relativism and irrationalism. What a pity, indeed …
5. Michael Beresford Foster, The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel, New York, 1965, 132. [1935]
See: “When the wars and civil wars of the twentieth century had destroyed the old Europe and removed it from the center of the world, the question remained as to what contribution Hegel had made to consideration of the new direction taken by history since 1800. Was Hegel the philosopher who had recognized the emancipatory tendencies of civil society but, faced with the contradictions of development, had sought refuge in once more affirming the positive role of the state? Or had he appealed to the regulatory function of the state in a conservative or rather pro–governmental frame of mind? With his recourse to metaphysical solutions had he helped to pave the way for the most diverse varieties of totalitarianism? Or could not on the contrary the young Hegel at least be ranged on the side of those protesting against the senselessness of the present–day world, or at all events calling for a new experience of history and historicity?”
Otto Pöggeler, “Editorial Introduction,” Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: The First Philosophy of Right, Heidelberg 1817–1818, With Additions From the Lectures of 1818–1819, J. Michael Stewart & Peter C. Hodgson, translators, Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Kurt Rainer Meist, Friedrich Hogemann, Hans Josef Schneider, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme & Hans Christian Lucas, editors, Oxford, 2012, 4. [1983 & 1995]
The twentieth century had destroyed the old Europe and removed it from the center of the world? Otto Pöggeler does not notice that Continental Europe was never at the “center of the world.” The British Empire was at the center of the world, not as “old Europe” but as the Industrial Revolution, precisely because of its profound integration with the New World. Pöggeler and his friends at the Hegel Archiv (Habermas and company), undoubtedly are blinded by the Napoléonic and French revolutionary conception of right, and therefore they fail to notice the profound difference between Bonapartism and the rational conception of right found in the Magna Carta. These are hard words and bound to roil the Eurocentrics in the House of Commons, the present–day relics of David Lloyd George. What do we care? The rational conception of right found in the Magna Carta, the political and economic fountainhead of the Industrial Revolution, is uplifted in the Constitution of the United States of America, as the bastion of world civilization. The American Civil War unchained the political and economic Idea of universal freedom from the modern coils of Bonapartism in the arena of world history. Modern European raison d’état is Bonapartism, which follows in the footsteps of Machiavellism, especially in the philosophical sophistry of Locke, Leibniz, Hume and Kant, and is therefore political and economic irrationalism: “The absolutist doctrines, in their application, lead rulers to the same results as the doctrines of Machiavelli (les doctrines absolutistes, dans leur application, conduisent les princes aux mêmes résultats que les doctrines de Machiavel).” This at least is the inescapable lesson of 20th century world history.
6. Michael Beresford Foster, Ibidem, 164.
7. Foster, Ibidem, 131–133.
8. Foster, Ibidem, 166.
9. Foster, Ibidem, 123.
10. Foster, Ibidem, 123–124.
11. Foster, Ibidem, 193.
12. Foster, Ibidem, 200.
13. Foster, Ibidem,
14. Foster, Ibidem, 91.
15. Foster, Ibidem, 204.
16. Foster, Ibidem, 203.
17. Foster, Ibidem.
18. Benedetto Croce, What Is Living and What Is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel, 3rd edition, Douglas Ainslie, translator, London, 1915, 50–110–182–201. [1906]
See: “Hegel was the culmination of the movement in German philosophy that started from Kant; although he [Hegel] often criticized Kant, his system could never have arisen if Kant’s had not existed … The identification of the real and the rational leads unavoidably to some of the complacency inseparable from the belief that ‘whatever is, is right’… All these quotations are from the introduction to The Philosophy of History … [Hegel’s] is a very superfine brand of freedom. It does not mean that you will be able to keep out of a concentration camp. It does not imply democracy, or a free press, or any of the usual Liberal watchwords, which Hegel rejects with contempt … I doubt whether, in Hegel’s opinion, a man could be a ‘hero’ without being a military conqueror. Hegel’s emphasis on nations, together with his peculiar conception of ‘freedom,’ explains his glorification of the State — a very important aspect of his political philosophy, to which we must now turn our attention. His philosophy of the State is developed both in his Philosophy of History and in his Philosophy of Law … Hegel’s doctrine of the State — [is] a doctrine which, if accepted, justifies every internal tyranny and every external aggression that can possibly be imagined. The strength of his bias appears in the fact that his theory is largely inconsistent with his own metaphysic, and that the inconsistencies are all such as tend to the justification of cruelty and international brigandage. A man may be pardoned if logic compels him regretfully to reach conclusions which he deplores, but not for departing from logic in order to be free to advocate crimes … Hegel thought that, if enough was known about a thing to distinguish it from all other things, then all its properties could be inferred by logic. This was a mistake, and from this mistake arose the whole imposing edifice of his system.”
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, History of Western Philosophy and its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day, London, 1947, 757–758–763–764–766–768–772.
See also: “What, then, is the difference between Kant and Hegel? … Kant opposes the knowledge of phenomena to the knowledge of things in themselves, the latter being knowledge that only pure rational cognition could offer us … Hegel pushes the critique of representation inaugurated by Immanuel Kant, to its very end. Kant revolutionized philosophy by asserting that thought is not regulated by its object, but rather the opposite is true. Hegel engages in this new path, and affirms that thought is unto itself its very own object. Hegel advances Kant’s Copernican revolution, while at the same time, he smashes it into pieces. What remains, according to Hegel (his greatest discovery) is the tension between the unity of the I think and the unthought multiplicity, or the multiplicity which is not completely unified by thought. Every object (thought) carries within itself this tension, which is why every object carries contradiction within itself, and is contradictory. The rôle of the doctrine of essence, its explosive force within the Hegelian system, is that the philosophy of Hegel reposes upon this tension; the function of which is to unfold its successive forms, without itself ever being surpassed. There is no exact determination of the nature of contradiction in the world, outside of this transition from the nature of being into the nature of essence. This is proved by Hegel’s critique of Heraclitus … ‘truth or universality is not yet expressed: It is the concept of unity as opposition per se, but it is not the concept of unity reflected into itself.’ (Note 7: Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, §18, p. 337) … Hegel tries to prove that unity can be known only on the condition of understanding being as the being of thought; unity is, as being, thought which thinks of being as thought (‘unity reflected in itself’) … Hegel’s distinction between the Hegelian dialectic and the Heraclitean dialectic is essential. It will play a very important rôle in the understanding of the Hegelian logic as a method of thought. Thus, for example, when Karl Marx uses the traditional Hegelian dialectic to combat universal change … Is Hegel left unscathed when the concept is unfolded across the entire Hegelian system? Probably not … For the last book of Hegel’s Logic, I have made my own translations.”
Béatrice Longuenesse, Hegel et la critique de la métaphysique: Étude sur la doctrine de l’essence, Paris, 1981, 10–17–51–52–208–209: “Où est, alors, la différence entre Kant et Hegel? … [Kant] oppose à la connaissance des phénomènes une connaissance des choses en soi que seule une pensée purement rationnelle pourrait nous offrir … Hegel pousse à son terme une critique de la représentation que Kant ne fait que amorcer. Kant a révolutionné la philosophie en affirmant que la pensée ne se règle pas sur son objet, mais l’inverse … Hegel s’engouffre dans la voie ouverte, et affirme que la pensée est à elle–même son propre objet. Il prolonge la révolution copernicienne, en même temps qu’il la fait voler en éclats … Ce qui reste, selon lui [Hegel], une découverte inestimable, est la tension entre l’unité du Je pense et la multiplicité non pensée, ou non complètement unifiée par la pensée. Tout objet (pensé) porte en soi cette tension, c’est pourquoi tout objet porte en soi la contradiction … L’intérêt de la Doctrine de l’essence, sa force explosive à l’intérieure du système hégélien, tiennent à ce qu’elle est tout entier bâtie sur cette tension; son objet est d’en exposer les forms successives, sans que jamais elle soit supprimée … Il n’y a pas de détermination rigoureuse de la nature de la contradiction dans les choses, en dehors de cette transposition du registre de l’être dans celui de l’essence. C’est ce que montre la critique formulée par Hegel à l’encontre d’Héraclite … ‘la vérité, l’universalité n’est pas encore exprimée; c’est le concept de l’unité étant dans l’opposition, non de l’unité réfléchie dans soi’ (Note 7: Hegel, Leçons d’histoire de la philosophie, §18, p. 337) … Hegel veut montrer, au contraire, que l’unité ne peut être saisie qu’à condition de comprendre l’être comme être pensée; l’unité est, dans l’être, la pensée pensant l’être (‘l’unité réfléchie dans soi’) … Ce clivage entre dialectique hégélienne et dialectique héraclitéenne est essentiel. Il jouera un rôle très important dans la compréhension de la logique hégélienne comme méthode de pensée. Ainsi par exemple, lorsque Marx revendique l’héritage de la dialectique hégélienne contre le mobilisme universel … [Hegel] échappe–t–il, en particulier, lorsque le concept se déploie dans le système tout entier? Peut–être pas … Pour ce dernier livre de la Logique, j’ai toujours donné ma propre traduction.”
See: Béatrice Longuenesse, éditrice, “Préface,” Vladimir Lénine: Textes philosophiques, Sylvie Pelta & Françoise Sève, traductrices, Paris, Éditions sociales/Messidor, 1982. [1978]
See finally: “The primary focus of Hegel’s discussion of the state in organic terms is the political constitution of the state. In this context, Hegel talks of the state as an organism not because it is a whole of which its individual citizens are parts, but rather that the elements that make up the constitution of the state depend on one another in the way that the categories that comprise the Concept are dependent on one another: ‘Note 64: While the powers of the state must certainly be distinguished, each must form a whole in itself and contain the other moments within it. When we speak of the distinct activities of these powers, we must not fall into the monumental error of taking this to mean that each power should exist independently and in abstraction; on the contrary, the powers should be distinguished only as moments of the concept,’ (Philosophy of Right, §272 Zusätze). Put very simply, this means that while the monarchy is a manifestation of individuality, the executive is a manifestation of particularity, and the legislature is a manifestation of universality, each also embodies aspects of the other ‘moments’ (so, for example, the monarch acts as an individual, but in his person represents the universal interest, where that interest involves the interest of a state comprising different particular groups). Thus, the conception of the universal that Hegel is using here is concrete in the sense that it cannot be conceived as something separable from the categories of particularity and individuality … Hegel’s position could be said to have philosophical value in offering a potential solution to certain familiar metaphysical problems (concerning the question of individuation, or the relation between substances and their attributes, for example).”
Robert Stern, “Hegel, British Idealism, and the Curious Case of the Concrete Universal,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15.1(2007): 141–142.
It goes without saying that the statement by Robert Stern to the effect that, “Hegel’s position could be said to have philosophical value in offering a potential solution to certain familiar metaphysical problems,” does not mean: Hegel’s position is said to have philosophical value in offering a potential solution to certain familiar metaphysical problems. The former statement therefore most certainly does not mean: Hegel’s position has philosophical value in offering a solution to certain familiar metaphysical problems. Wherefore? Modern sophists like Robert Stern ignore and neglect the rational distinction between the genuine Hegel and Pure Hegelism of the originalausgabe on the one hand, and the pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism of their impure Hegelianism on the other hand.
I am reminded of Vladimir Zeman and his Kant Seminar some 20 years ago in Montréal, when he used to praise Kant to high–heaven as the “father of the contemporary scientific spirit,” and who treated the school of Hegel as the bastion of 20th century totalitarianism: Along with Stanley French and his Clique of French phenomenologists, they gave the admirers of Hegel no quarter, unless by Hegelianism one means marxisme.
See: “It must be acknowledged that phenomenology [subjective idealism] is, nevertheless, well represented in Canada, and that there is a present and energetic level of activity, organization, and research … [phenomenology] shows no signs of fading away and continues to thrive, albeit somewhat quietly … there are currently a number of centers, institutes, and societies with a focus on phenomenology, or Continental thought in the wider scope … given the current levels of activity, and the promise of continued interest and involvement on the part of students and younger academics, a solid future for phenomenology in Canada is assured.”
Linda Fisher, “Canada,” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, Lester Embree, et alia, editors, Dordrecht, 1997, 91–94, 91–91–91–94.
See: “[Phenomenologists] are critical of Hegel’s goal of ‘absolute knowledge,’ the identity of thought and Being, which they regard as spirit’s totalizing comprehension of some first–order truth about what there is. They thus reproach Hegel for what appears to be the organizing principle for his Phänomenologie, viz., his so–called metaphysical monism, because, as phenomenologists, their primary philosophical interest, allegedly unlike Hegel’s, is not the coherence of an intellectual system establishing a supersensible entity (Divine Mind) that both explains and coincides with the sensible or historical world.”
Frank M. Kirkland, “Hegel,” Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, Lester Embree, et alia, editors, Dordrecht, 1997, 292–298, 292–293.
Phenomenologists, according to the Encyclopedia of Phenomenology, attack (criticize and reproach) Hegel because his philosophy does not interest them. Undoubtedly these same phenomenologists uphold subjective idealism because modern irrationalism interests them. The modern sophists, namely the schools of Jean–Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir and so forth, in the public universities, the media and politics, especially in Europe and the United States, have long attacked Washington as totalizing, absolutistic, imperialistic, conservative and totalitarian, especially at Lord Russell’s War Crimes Tribunal. They follow in the footsteps of modern subjectivism, relativism and irrationalism:
“Jean–Paul Sartre and myself have always been perfectly clear on this point: It is not because there is a desire to exist that this desire corresponds to reality as such. This is proved beyond doubt in Kant’s intellectual philosophy: The belief in causation is no basis for the belief in a Supreme Cause. Man desires to exist, which does not mean therefore that he could ever reach existence, or even that existence is a possible notion: Of course, we speak of being and existence as reflection. We refer to the synthesis between being and existence which is impossible. Sartre and I, we have always taught this doctrine, which is the very foundation of our philosophy: Out of timber so crooked as that from which man is made nothing entirely straight can be built.”
Simone de Beauvoir in Madeleine Gobeil, “Entrevue avec Simone de Beauvoir,” Cité Libre: Nouvelle série, 16(15).69(août–septembre, 1964): 30–31: “Nous avons toujours dit, Sartre et moi, que ce n’est pas parce qu’il y a désir d’être, que ce désir corresponde à une réalité quelconque. C’est comme Kant le disait, sur le plan intellectuel. Ce n’est pas une raison parce qu’on croit à des causalités pour qu’il y ait une cause suprême. Ce n’est pas parce qu’il y a chez l’homme un désir d’être pour qu’il puisse jamais atteindre l’être, ou même que l’être soit une notion possible, l’être en tout cas qui soit réflexion et en même temps existence. II y a une synthèse existence et être qui est impossible. Nous l’avons répété toute notre vie, Sartre et moi, et c’est le fond de notre pensée, il y a un creux dans l’homme et même ses réalisations ont ce creux en elles.”
Modern sophists have thereby greatly enriched themselves and their backers over the years, the inferior ruling classes. Meanwhile, the defenders of America and the Western democracies in the struggle against world communism are abused as war–mongers and baby–killers.
Phenomenology is about the the re–definition of words such as being, existence, love, jealousy, emotion and so forth, according to what is named the “phenomenological method,” which is modern sophistry. Since the realm of exact historiography and world history is not subjective idealism, phenomenologists create sophistical historical distinctions in order to separate phenomenology from modern unreason:
“[Kant’s] phenomenology was clearly nothing but what he called ‘Critique of Pure Reason’ … Nevertheless, such a critique of human knowledge has by itself little if any affinity with today’s full–fledged phenomenology … Husserl found himself increasingly in sympathy and agreement precisely with Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, apparently without being aware of the fact that there was even a terminological bridge for his latter–day rapprochement to Kant’s critical philosophy.”
Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, vol. 1, Dordrecht, 1960, 12.
Kant’s critical philosophy is not sophistry? Phenomenologists are not outside of world history and the arena of politics and economics: Phenomenologists thus re–define words for their backers, the inferior ruling classes. Phenomenologists who maintain the contrary, namely that they re–define words for the superior ruling classes, have not learned the inescapable lesson of exact historiography and world history: Subjective idealism in 20th century politics and economics is not absolute idealism. In other words, absolute idealism is not impure Hegelianism, among other things: Reason, in the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism, rises above the limitations of the understanding and resolves them as the true Notion.
See finally: “[Hegel] accepted Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness in … [his] own thought but, in contrast to Kant … [Hegel] evaluated it positively … [Hegel] recognized in it Reason’s special capacity to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding …. with his Logic Hegel seeks to bring the transcendental philosophy initiated by Kant to its conclusion.”
Hans–Georg Gadamer, Hegel’s Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, translated with an introduction by P. Christopher Smith, New Haven, 1976, 5–5–5–5–76. [1971]
The genuine Hegel recognized (1) in Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness, the special capacity of Reason to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding, otherwise Hegel recognized (2) in the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason, the special capacity of Reason to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding, otherwise, Hegel recognized (3) in both Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness and in the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason, the special capacity of Reason to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding. Therefore, Hegel positively evaluated (1) Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness, otherwise Hegel positively evaluated (2) the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason, otherwise, Hegel positively evaluated (3) both Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness and the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason. Therefore Hegel seeks to bring the transcendental philosophy initiated by Kant to its conclusion with the Hegelian Logic? Of course, this is not the place for a rigorous exposition of the Pure Hegelian refutation of the hermeneutical dialectics of Gadamer, which is contained in the Stronghold of Hegel, in the chapter which is entitled “Contre Gadamer,” 436 ff.
If Hegel recognized in Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness, and if he recognized in the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason, the special capacity of Reason to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding, namely, if Hegel positively evaluated Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness as the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason, then Hegel seeks to bring the transcendental philosophy initiated by Kant to its conclusion with the Hegelian Logic? Therefore it is not the case that the genuine Hegel greatly recognized in the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason (beyond the so–called demonstration of Kant), the special capacity of Reason to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding, if Hegel positively evaluated Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness as the necessary self–contradictoriness of reason.
Gadamer’s “necessary contradictoriness of reason” is beyond the genuine Hegelian dialectic because Reason possesses a “special capacity to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding.” The genuine Hegel did not therefore recognize in Kant’s demonstration of reason’s necessary self–contradictoriness, Reason’s special capacity to transcend the limits of a kind of thought which fails to rise above the limits of the understanding: The necessary contradictoriness of reason of the Kantian dialectic is therefore not the same necessary contradictoriness of Reason of the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelianism. The Pure Hegelian dialectical necessity is not the Kantian dialectical necessity: The Pure Hegelian dialectical necessity is absolute, while the Kantian dialectical necessity is subjective. The genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelianism did not therefore recognize the necessary self–contradictoriness of absolute dialectical rationality in the subjective dialectical necessity of Kantian irrationalism: In his Logic Hegel does not seek to bring the transcendental philosophy initiated by Kant to its conclusion. The rational distinction between Kant and Hegel is found in the Pure Hegelian philosophy.
It is a mistake to regard Hegel’s philosophy as nothing more than the logical outcome of Kant’s system: “The essentials of Hegel’s philosophy are to be found in Plato and Aristotle … all that he did was to make a new synthesis of them with such modifications as modern knowledge required,” (Hiralal Haldar, 1927, 10).
See: “The influence of Greek philosophy on Hegel, particularly of Plato and Aristotle, must not be overlooked … it is not difficult to defend the thesis that the essentials of Hegel’s philosophy are to be found in Plato and Aristotle and that all that he did was to make a new synthesis of them with such modifications as modern knowledge required. The beginning, for example, of his logic, all that he says about being and nothing, will be found almost in identical terms in Plato’s Parmenides.”
Hiralal Haldar, Neo–Hegelianism, London, 1927, 10.
Considering Hans–Georg Gadamer’s place in the Cold War struggle and his place in the strife between Western and Soviet Marxism in East and West Germany, his submission to Hitler and then Stalin, and considering his relations to Heidegger and modern European political and economic irrationalism, his dialectical hermeneutics therefore constitutes part of the beginning of the movement away from modern 20th century German unreason, in the world historical rise of Americanism:
“From the standpoint of the philosophy of finitude, it’s possible for us to acquire historical consciousness again without falling prey to historical relativism, exactly to the extent that we recognize the limits of all knowledge, which is bounded precisely by its own historical situation. This recognition gives us back the possibility of seeing the past from our historical perspective, a possibility that I called the ‘fusion of horizons.’ Yet the meaning of our finitude doesn’t exhaust itself in this alone. What I had already tried to show Heidegger in Marburg and later developed further in the Lisbon lecture and in other essays was, as I have already said, that the genuine meaning of our finitude or our ‘thrownness’ consists in the fact that we become aware, not only of our being historically conditioned, but especially of our being conditioned by the other. Precisely in our ethical relation to the other, it becomes clear to us how difficult it is to do justice to the demands of the other or even simply to become aware of them. The only way not to succumb to our finitude is to open ourselves to the other, to listen to the ‘thou’ who stands before us.”
Hans–Georg Gadamer in Riccardo Dottori, A Century of Philosophy: Hans–Georg Gadamer in Conversation With Riccardo Dottori, Rod Coltman and Sigrid Koepke, translators, New York, Continuum, 2006, 29. [2000]
From the standpoint of the philosophy of finitude? “Hegel brought to its completion the development of traditional logic into a transcendental ‘logic of objectivity’―a development which began with Fichte’s ‘Doctrine of Science.’ But the language–ness of all thought continues to demand that thought, moving in the opposite direction, convert the concept back into the valid word. The more radically objectifying thought reflects upon itself and unfolds the experience of dialectic, the more clearly it points to what it is not. Dialectic must retrieve itself in hermeneutics.”
Hans–Georg Gadamer, Hegel’s Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, translated with an introduction by P. Christopher Smith, New Haven, 1976, 99. [1971]
Dialectic must retrieve itself in hermeneutics because the more radically objectifying thought reflects upon itself and unfolds the experience of dialectic, the more clearly it points to what it is not? Perhaps dialectic retrieves itself in hermeneutics, otherwise perhaps not. Wherefore? Dialectic must retrieve itself in hermeneutics, otherwise not.
The hermeneutical and dialectical conception of rationality is therefore not the fountainhead of Globalism in the world of today: Reason, in the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism, rises above the limitations of the understanding and resolves them as the true Notion.
See: Richard Wolin, “Nazism and the Complicities of Hans–Georg Gadamer: Untruth and Method,” The New Republic, 15 May 2000, 36–45.
See finally: “[Heidegger] rebuked me for traveling to America instead of writing my book on Plato. He later realized that he wasn’t entitled to rebuke me for this, because it was through me that he saw that he had been wrong to think of Plato’s relationship to Aristotle as he did … That was then the meaning of our [Heidegger’s and Gadamer’s] encounter with Hegel. This is where the essays in Hegel’s Dialectic come from. All of this came out of the time I was holding lectures in Leipzig. I was reading a great deal about Kant and Fichte and Schelling and Heidegger and, most of all, Hegel. All of it emerged during this period, after I had developed my idea about Plato’s dialectic being an ethical thesis.”
Hans–Georg Gadamer in Riccardo Dottori, A Century of Philosophy: Hans–Georg Gadamer in Conversation With Riccardo Dottori, Rod Coltman and Sigrid Koepke, translators, New York, 2006, 29. [2000]
19. Michael Beresford Foster, Ibidem, 195–196.
20. Foster, Ibidem, 196.
21. Foster, Ibidem.
22. Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator, “The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, By Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, Chicago, 1960, §344, 111.
See: “Die Staaten, Völker und Individuen in diesem Geschäfte des Weltgeistes stehen in ihrem besonderen bestimmten Prinzipe auf, das an ihrer Verfassung und der ganzen Breite ihres Zustandes seine Auslegung und Wirklichkeit hat, deren sie sich bewußt und in deren Interesse vertieft, sie zugleich bewußtlose Werkzeuge und Glieder jenes inneren Geschäfts sind, worin diese Gestalten vergehen, der Geist an und für sich aber sich den Übergang in seine nächste höhere Stufe vorbereitet und erarbeitet.”
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Zum Gebrauch für seine Vorlesungen, Berlin, 1821, §344, 345–346.
See also: Hegel, Philosophische Bibliothek: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Neu herausgegeben von Georg Lasson, Band 124, Leipzig, 1911, §344, 272.
See finally: “Die Staaten, Völker und Individuen in diesem Geschäfte des Weltgeistes stehen in ihrem besonderen bestimmten Prinzipe auf, das an ihrer Verfassung und der ganzen Breite ihres Zustandes seine Auslegung und Wirklichkeit hat, deren sie sich bewußt und in deren Interesse vertieft, sie zugleich bewußtlose Werkzeuge und Glieder jenes inneren Geschäfts sind, worin diese Gestalten vergehen, der Geist an und für sich aber sich den Übergang in seine nächste höhere Stufe vorbereitet und erarbeitet.”
Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit Hegels eigenhändigen Randbemerkungen in seinem Handexemplar der Rechtsphilosophie, Vierte Auflage, Johannes Hoffmeister, Herausgegeber, Hamburg, 1967, §344, 290. [1955]
23. Thomas Malcolm Knox, Ibidem, §347 Anmerkung, 111.
See: “Die spezielle Geschichte eines welthistorischen Volks enthält teils die Entwickelung seines Prinzips von seinem kindlichen eingehüllten Zustande aus bis zu seiner Blüte, wo es zum freien sittlichen Selbstbewußtsein gekommen, nun in die allgemeine Geschichte eingreift, ― teils auch die Periode des Verfalls und Verderbens; ― denn so bezeichnet sich an ihm das Hervorgehen eines höheren Prinzips als nur des Negativen seines eigenen. Damit wird der Übergang des Geistes in jenes Prinzip und so der Weltgeschichte an ein anderes Volk angedeutet …”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §347 Anmerkung, 347. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §347 Anmerkung, 273.
24. Knox, Ibidem, §348, 111.
See: “An der Spitze aller Handlungen, somit auch der welthistorischen, stehen Individuen als die das Substantielle verwirklichenden Subjektivitäten. Als diesen Lebendigkeiten der substantiellen Tat des Weltgeistes, und so unmittelbar identisch mit derselben, ist sie ihnen selbst verborgen und nicht Objekt und Zweck.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §348, 347–348. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §348, 274.
25. Knox, Ibidem, §348, 111.
See: “Als diesen Lebendigkeiten der substantiellen Tat des Weltgeistes und so unmittelbar identisch mit derselben, ist sie ihnen selbst verborgen und nicht Objekt und Zweck; sie haben auch die Ehre derselben und Dank nicht bei ihrer Mitwelt (ebendas.), noch bei der öffentlichen Meinung der Nachwelt, sondern als formelle Subjektivitäten nur bei dieser Meinung ihren Teil als unsterblichen Ruhm.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §348, 348. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911.
26. Knox, Ibidem, §345, 111.
See: “Die Weltgeschichte fällt außer diesen Gesichtspunkten; in ihr erhält dasjenige notwendige Moment der Idee des Weltgeistes, welches gegenwärtig seine Stufe ist, sein absolutes Recht, und das darin lebende Volk und dessen Taten erhalten ihre Vollführung, und Glück und Ruhm.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §345, 346. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §345, 272–273.
27. Knox, Ibidem.
See: “In ihr erhält dasjenige notwendige Moment der Idee des Weltgeistes, welches gegenwärtig seine Stufe ist, sein absolutes Recht, und das darin lebende Volk und dessen Taten erhalten ihre Vollführung, und Glück und Ruhm.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §345, 346. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §345, 272–273.
28. Knox, Ibidem, §353, 112.
See: “Das Prinzip der vierten Gestaltung ist das Umschlagen dieses Gegensatzes des Geistes, in seiner Innerlichkeit seine Wahrheit und konkretes Wesen zu empfangen und in der Objektivität einheimisch und versöhnt zu sein, und weil dieser zur ersten Substantialität zurückgekommene Geist der aus dem unendlichen Gegensatze zurückgekehrte ist, diese seine Wahrheit als Gedanke und als Welt gesetzlicher Wirklichkeit zu erzeugen und zu wissen.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §353, 350. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §353, 275–276.
29. Knox, Ibidem, §347A 111.
See: “Die spezielle Geschichte eines welthistorischen Volks enthält teils die Entwickelung seines Prinzips von seinem kindlichen eingehüllten Zustande aus bis zu seiner Blüte, wo es zum freien sittlichen Selbstbewußtsein gekommen, nun in die allgemeine Geschichte eingreift.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §347A, 347. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §347A, 273.
30. Knox, Ibidem, §345, 111.
See: “In ihr erhält dasjenige notwendige Moment der Idee des Weltgeistes, welches gegenwärtig seine Stufe ist, sein absolutes Recht, und das darin lebende Volk und dessen Taten erhalten ihre Vollführung, und Glück und Ruhm.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §345, 346. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §345, 272–273.
31. Knox, Ibidem, §347, 111.
See: “Dem Volke, dem solches Moment als natürliches Prinzip zukommt, ist die Vollstreckung desselben in dem Fortgange des sich entwickelnden Selbstbewußtseins des Weltgeistes übertragen. Dieses Volk ist in der Weltgeschichte, für diese Epoche, — und es kann in ihr nur einmal Epoche machen, — das Herrschende.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §347, 346–347. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §347, 273.
32. Knox, Ibidem, §343, 110.
See: “Die Geschichte des Geistes ist seine Tat, denn er ist nur, was er tut, und seine Tat ist, sich und zwar hier als Geist sich zum Gegenstande seines Bewußtseins zu machen, sich für sich selbst auslegend zu erfassen. Dies Erfassen ist sein Sein und Prinzip, und die Vollendung eines Erfassens ist zugleich seine Entäußerung und sein Übergang. Der, formell ausgedrückt, von neuem dies Erfassen erfassende, und was dasselbe ist, aus der Entäußerung in sich gehende Geist, ist der Geist der höheren Stufe gegen sich, wie er in jenem ersteren Erfassen stand.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §343, 344–345. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §343, 271–272.
33. Knox, Ibidem, §343A, 111.
See: “Aber denen, welche diesen Gedanken verwerfen, ist der Geist ein leeres Wort geblieben, sowie die Geschichte ein oberflächliches Spiel zufälliger, sogenannter nur menschlicher Bestrebungen und Leidenschaften. Wenn sie dabei auch in den Ausdrücken von Vorsehung und Plan der Vorsehung den Glauben eines höheren Waltens aussprechen, so bleiben dies unerfüllte Vorstellungen, indem sie auch ausdrücklich den Plan der Vorsehung für ein ihnen Unerkennbares und Unbegreifliches ausgeben.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §343A, 345. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §343A, 272.
34. Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince, Luigi Ricci, translator, Oxford, 1921, 44–71–71–99–100–101–102–105.
35. Knox, Ibidem, §347A, 111.
See: “Eine Periode, von welcher aus jenes Volk das absolute Interesse verloren hat, das höhere Prinzip zwar dann auch positiv in sich aufnimmt und sich hineinbildet, aber darin als in einem Empfangenen nicht mit immanenter Lebendigkeit und Frische sich verhält, — vielleicht seine Selbständigkeit verliert, vielleicht auch sich als besonderer Staat oder ein Kreis von Staaten fortsetzt oder fortschleppt und in mannigfaltigen inneren Versuchen und äußeren Kämpfen nach Zufall herumschlägt.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §347A, 347. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §347A, 273.
36. Knox, Ibidem, §347, 111.
See: “Gegen dies sein absolutes Recht, Träger der gegenwärtigen Entwickelungsstufe des Weltgeistes zu sein, sind die Geister der anderen Völker rechtlos, und sie, wie die, deren Epoche vorbei ist, zählen nicht mehr in der Weltgeschichte.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §347, 347. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §347, 273.
37. Richard Burdon, Viscount Haldane, “Introductory Preface,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, vol. 1, By Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Walter Henry Johnston and Leslie Graham Struthers, translators, London, 1929, 7–9.
See: “Hegel writes as though he were divided from Kant by a mighty gulf …The Absolute as Absolute stands revealed, but not as an object perceived.”
Richard Burdon, Viscount Haldane, “Hegel,” The Contemporary Review, 67(February, 1895): 237–242.
See also: “L’humanité a jusqu’ici vécu sur la réponse à priori qu’elle a dû se faire dans son enfance, alors que manquaient les éléments d’une solution à posteriori.”
George Clemenceau, “Appendice,” Notions d’anatomie et de physiologie: De la Génération des Éléments anatomiques, Charles Robin, Introduction, Paris, 1867, 279. See: George Clemenceau, “Appendice,” De la Génération des Éléments anatomiques, Paris, 1865, 221.
See: “Nous avions livré au Napoléon, après le coup d’État, tout ce qui faisait la force morale de la France dans le monde, ses traditions historiques de pensée, et, avec toutes nos garanties de contrôle, les principes vivants de notre Révolution, du droit, de justice et de liberté … Fermons les Codes, Français, plus de lois, plus de justice, suivons, les yeux bandés, le chef inepte, au flair d’artilleur, vers les recommencements de Sedan et de Metz!”
Georges Clemenceau, Vers la réparation, Paris, 1899, 94–503.
See also: “L’homme parlant, il est vrai, fait résonner le mot droit, formule magique d’un idéal d’équité dont rien ne fournit le spectacle sur la terre.”
Georges Clemenceau, La France devant l’Allemagne, Paris, 1918, 11.
See also: “I have always regarded Immanuel Kant not only as a very powerful thinker, but as the metaphysical father of the philosophy of positivism … undoubtedly the greatest and most positive advance that I have made since Kant is the discovery of the evolution of human ideas according to the law of three stages, namely the theological, metaphysical and scientific phases: The Kantian philosophy in my opinion is the very basis of the three stages of positivism.” (xxi)
[ J’avais toujours regardé Kant non–seulement comme une très–forte tête, mais comme le métaphysicien le plus rapproché de la philosophie positive … le pas le plus positif et le plus distinct que j’ai fait après lui, me semble seulement d’avoir découverte la loi du passage des idées humaines par les trois états théologique, métaphysique, et scientifique, loi qui me semble être la base dont Kant à conseillé l’exécution ]
Auguste Comte (10 December 1824) in Maximilian Friedrich Müller, “Translator’s Preface,” Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: A Commemoration of the Centenary of Its First Publication, vol. 1, London, 1881, v–lxii, xxi: “‘J’ai lu et relu avec un plaisir infini le petit traité de Kant (Idee zu einer allgemeinen Geschichte in weltbürgerlicher Absicht, 1784); il est prodigieux pour I’époque, et même, si je I’avais connu six ou sept ans plus tot, il m’aurait épargné de la peine. Je suis charmé que vous I’ayez traduit, il peut très–efficacement contribuer à préparer les esprits à la philosophie positive. La conception générale ou au moins la méthode y est encore métaphysique, mais les détails montrent à chaque instant I’esprit positif. J’avais toujours regardé Kant non–seulement comme une très–forte tête, mais comme le métaphysicien le plus rapproché de la philosophie positive … Pour moi, je ne me trouve jusqu’à present, après cette lecture, d’autre valeur que celle d’avoir systématisé et arrêté la conception ébauchée par Kant à mon insu, ce que je dois surtout à I’éducation scientifique; et même le pas le plus positif et le plus distinct que j’ai fait après lui, me semble seulement d’avoir découverte la loi du passage des idées humaines par les trois états théologique, métaphysique, et scientifique, loi qui me semble être la base dont Kant à conseillé l’exécution. Je rends grâce aujourd’hui à mon défaut d’érudition; car si mon travail, tel qu’il est maintenant, avait été précédé chez moi par I’étude du traité de Kant, il aurait, à mes propres yeux, beaucoup perdu de sa valeur.’ See Auguste Comte, par É. Littré, Paris, 1864, p. 154; Lettre de Comte à M. d’Eichthal, 10 Déc. 1824.”
See also: “The positivist philosophy was a reaction to the speculative phase that developed in philosophy after Kant.”
Dagobert David Runes, Vergilius Ferm, Kurt Friedrich Leidecker and John White, editors, “Auguste Comte: Positive Philosophy,” Treasury of Philosophy, New York, 1955, 260–267, 261.
See also: “The absolute [of Hegel] became a stumbling–block to Ludwig Andreas Feuerbach and other members of the ‘Left.’ They rejected as an illegitimate interpolation the eternal subject of development, and, instead of one continuing God as the subject of all the predicates by which in the logic the absolute is defined, assumed only a series of ideas, products of philosophic activity. They denied the theological value of the logical forms ― the development of these forms being in their opinion due to the human thinker, not to a self–revealing absolute. Thus they made man the creator of the absolute. But with this modification on the system another necessarily followed; a mere logical series could not create nature. And thus the material universe became the real starting–point. Thought became only the result of organic conditions — subjective and human.”
William Wallace 1844–1897, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 11th edition, vol. 13, New York, 1911, 205.
See also: “[Those] theistic Hegelians who maintain the personality of God in a world beyond our sphere, must, for consistency’s sake, deny that God is cognizable. But how then can they remain in the (Hegelian) school?”
Karl Ludwig Michelet in Anonymous, “Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz: The Life of Hegel,” The Biblical Repertory and Princeton Review, 20.4(October, 1848): 585.
See also: “[Hegel] was a thoroughly anti–critical, anti–revolutionary philosopher … Hegel’s teaching had been taken up by the Left in a one–sided and abstract way; and the great majority of people always prefer what one can become fanatical about, and this is never anything but what is abstract.”
Johann Eduard Erdmann 1805–1892, A History of Philosophy: German Philosophy Since Hegel, 4th German edition, vol. 3, London, 1899, 66–81.
See also: “It is the twentieth century that has a last shaken the [Kantio–] Hegelian concept of the historical process whereby ‘everything real is rational.’ It was this concept, violently debated for decades, that Russian thinkers of the past century finally accepted. But now, at the height of the state’s triumph over individual freedom, Russian thinkers wearing padded camp jackets have dethroned and cast down the old Hegelian law.”
Vasily Grossman in Stéphane Courtois, editor & contributor, “Why?” The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression, Karel Bartošek, Sylvain Boulouque, Pascal Fontaine, Rémi Kauffer, Martin Malia, Jean–Louis Margolin, Andrzej Paczkowski, Jean–Louis Panné, Pierre Rigoulot, Yves Santamaria & Nicolas Werth, contributors, Jonathan Murphy & Mark Kramer, translators, Mark Kramer, consulting editor, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 756–757. [Italics added] See: “It has been written that ‘history is the science of human misfortune.’ Our bloodstained century of violence amply confirms this statement … The United States remains heavily influenced by a culture of violence deeply rooted in two major historical tragedies―the enslavement of black Africans and the extermination of Native Americans.”
Stéphane Courtois, editor & contributor, “The Crimes of Communism,” The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression, Karel Bartošek, Sylvain Boulouque, Pascal Fontaine, Rémi Kauffer, Martin Malia, Jean–Louis Margolin, Andrzej Paczkowski, Jean–Louis Panné, Pierre Rigoulot, Yves Santamaria & Nicolas Werth, contributors, Jonathan Murphy & Mark Kramer (consulting editor), translators, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1999, 1.
See also: “The unfolded totality of the Hegelian school may be pictured in a brief compend. With the pseudo–Hegelians (Fichte, jun., Weisse, Brandis &c.,) perception under the form of faith or experience, is the sole source of positive religious truth. On the extreme right of the Hegelian school, perception, (as with Hinrichs) is the absolute criterion of the results found by means of logical thinking; while Göschel gives it still a decisive voice in all religious affairs. Schaller, Erdmann, and Gabler, who form the pure right side, allow to religious perception a consultative vote, which however, like a good ruler with his subjects, they never leave unrespected. Rosenkranz, who ushers in the centre, proceeds for the most part in accordance with the voice of perception, but in some cases rejects it. In Marheineke, the perception is the witness, who can only speak respecting the fact, while the question of law or right can only be decided by speculative thinking. On the left of the centre, (that taken by Vatke, Snellmann and Michelet) the perception is a true–hearted servant, who must subject herself obediently to reason as mistress. Strauss, on the left side, makes her a slave, while with Feuerbach and Bauer she appears verily as a paria.”
Karl Ludwig Michelet (1842) in John Daniel Morell, Historical and Critical View of the Speculative Philosophy of Europe in the Nineteenth Century, 2nd edition, 1 volume edition, New York, 1848, 481. [1846]
See finally: “It is asserted by some, that the three branches above mentioned (usually termed the right hand, the centre, and the left), exhibit the threefold movement of the dialectic process.”
John Daniel Morell, Ibidem, 480–481.
38. Knox, Ibidem, §§334–340, 109–110.
See: “Der Streit der Staaten kann deswegen, insofern die besonderen Willen keine Übereinkunft finden, nur durch Krieg entschieden werden … In das Verhältnis der Staaten gegeneinander, weil sie darin als besondere sind, fällt das höchst bewegte Spiel der inneren Besonderheit der Leidenschaften, Interessen, Zwecke, der Talente und Tugenden, der Gewalt, des Unrechts und der Laster, wie der äußeren Zufälligkeit, in den größten Dimensionen der Erscheinung.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §§334–340, 339–342. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §§334–340, 268–270.
39. Knox, Ibidem, §340, 110.
See: “Die Prinzipien der Volksgeister sind um ihrer Besonderheit willen, in der sie als existierende Individuen ihre objektive Wirklichkeit und ihr Selbstbewußtsein haben, überhaupt beschränkte, und ihre Schicksale und Taten in ihrem Verhältnisse zueinander sind die erscheinende Dialektik der Endlichkeit dieser Geister, aus welcher der allgemeine Geist, der Geist der Welt, als unbeschränkt ebenso sich hervorbringt, als er es ist, der sein Recht, — und sein Recht ist das allerhöchste, — an ihnen in der Weltgeschichte, als dem Weltgerichte, ausübt.”
Hegel, Ibidem, 1821, §340, 342–343. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §340, 270–271.
40. Michael Beresford Foster, The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel, New York, 1965, 196–197.
See: “Reference 2: §298, quoted p. 193, note 3, supra, and Reference 3: §280, Zusätze, quoted p. 191, note 1, supra.”
Foster, Ibidem, 196.
See finally: “[In The Philosophy of Right] the state so described is unlike any existing state in Hegel’s day. It is a form of limited monarchy, with parliamentary government, trial by jury and toleration for Jews and dissenters. In all these respects it differed from the contemporary Prussia. It has often been said by Hegel’s detractors that his book was written on the ‘dunghill of servility’ and that his ideal state is identified with the monarchy of Friedrich William III. Little historical knowledge and little study of Hegel is required to see that this is nonsense.”
Thomas Malcolm Knox, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, Chicago, 1967, 302.
41. Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, “Introduction: The Shape and Influence of Hegel’s Aesthetics,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures, Robert F. Brown, editor and translator, Oxford, 2014, 7–176; 32–36–36–36.
See: “After Hegel’s death, his former students came together with the rather noble thought of assembling various transcripts of the lecture series he gave and to which they had access, hoping to bring to the light of a general public the “system” that [they?] were convinced was completed for years and presented orally in the lecture hall. However, the methodologies through which they assembled these transcripts into standalone monographs, with the aid of Hegel’s own manuscripts for his lectures, is dubious at best. They paid little to no attention to changes between different lecture courses, combining them as they saw fit to guarantee the logical progression of the dialectical movement as they interpreted it. But without the original source material, it was impossible to test the suspicion that they may have falsified Hegel’s own views. Indeed, it was all we had to go on to have any understanding of his views. Now, however, many manuscripts and transcripts — even ones not available to his students — have been found. When one compares these manuscripts and transcripts with the lectures published by his students, the differences between them are in no case simply philological niceties … this information may drastically challenge our historical picture of Hegel.”
Sean J. McGrath and Joseph Carew, “Introduction: What Remains of German Idealism?” Rethinking German Idealism, Joseph Carew, Wes Furlotte, Jean–Christophe Goddard, Adrian Johnston, Cem Kömürcü, Sean J. McGrath, Constantin Rauer, Alexander Schnell, F. Scott Scribner, Devin Zane Shaw, Konrad Utz, Jason M. Wirth, contributors, London, Palgrave Macmillan, 2016, 1–19; 4.
See also: “The form in which this book [Philosophy of Right] presents itself has given it an air of dogmatism beyond what can properly be laid to the charge of its author. The Philosophy of Right contains the substance of lectures delivered by Hegel as professor. After its publication it served as a compendium on which Hegel lectured in succeeding years. And he thus made many oral additions, notes of which were taken by his pupils, and these notes were, after his death, thrown into the shape of paragraphs, annexed to the sections of the original work. The work, therefore, as we now have it, contains both the paragraphs written by the author, and also those embodying, as nearly as possible in the author’s words, what he said by way of illustration or explanation. This has given it a fragmentary and incomplete character, which is detrimental to its effect and has made many portions wear an appearance of inconclusiveness and precipitate assumption.”
Thomas Collett Sandars, “Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” Oxford Essays, Contributed by Members of the University, London, 1855, 216.
See finally: “Hegel’s works on politics and history merely elaborate part of his system — that part in which human mind objectifies itself in its endeavor to find an object identical with itself — and are unintelligible in isolation, they deserve separate treatment because they have become so famous, if not notorious.”
Thomas Malcolm Knox, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, Chicago, 1967, 302–303.
42. Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, Dordrecht, 2001, xvi–27–28–29–29.
See: “That Hegel does not conceive of spirit, soul, or God as separate entities is clear to anyone who has read his Philosophy of Religion … Only in cases where authentic texts are unavailable may they [Zusatze] be accepted as indications of Hegel’s answers to questions that are not treated in his handwritten or published work. If they contradict the explicit theory of the authorized texts, we can presume that the student is wrong, unless we can show that it is plausible that they express a change in the evolution of Hegel’s thought. On issues where Hegel left us without any authorized treatise (as is the case for large parts of the Aesthetics, the History of Philosophy, and the Philosophy of World History) we must, of course, use the surviving course notes as the only possible access to Hegel’s thought; but here, too, the ultimate criteria for their authenticity lie in the principles of his authorized work … ‘es ist der Gang Gottes in der Welt daß der Staat ist.’ Literally: ‘It is the course of God in the world that the state is’ … ‘God’ is used by Hegel as a more popular name for the universal and absolute spirit. His system presents the universe as one great movement or course (Gang) in which the spirit (or ‘God’) unfolds all of its possibilities (that is, logical, natural, spiritual, aesthetic, religious, and theoretical) … ‘It is the course of God [that causes or necessitates the fact] that nature or art or religion or the state exist’ … a journey with Hegel is certainly rewarding, but it does not quite reach the desired goal. The Good demands a higher ascent and a deeper descent because it exceeds and precedes the noëtic cosmos of ideas.”
Adriaan Peperzak, Ibidem, 12–29 ff.
Genuine Hegelianism, the true Gospel of Hegel which greatly influenced America over the years, especially in the Civil War, unlike impure Hegelianism, suspends judgement on matters where Hegel left us without any authorized treatise, because the speculative logical and dialectical system of the pure Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism comes only from the originalausgabe.
On issues where Hegel left us without any authorized treatise we must use the surviving course notes as the only possible access to Hegel’s thought, while the ultimate criteria for their authenticity lie in the principles of his authorized work (Ad Peperzak): Refutations of Hegel’s philosophy which contain as premises statements from the non–authorized work are not inferentially equivalent with arguments which contain as premises statements from Hegel’s authorized work because the former involve only the “possible access” to Hegel’s thought. The authenticity and “possible access” of such statements as premises lies in their reconciliation to the principles of the originalausgabe. But the interpretative determination, the hermeneutical judgement that entails the semantic reconciliation, that makes these non–authorized statements “authentic,” and therefore acceptable as premises in arguments against Hegel, does not thereby make them inferentially equivalent to the statements from the originalausgabe: They involve only the “possible access” to Hegel’s thought, whereas the latter involve the actual access to Hegel’s thought. In other words, the difference here between interpretative possibility and actuality entails the distinction between weaker and stronger levels of inference in the demonstrability of the refutation: A strong refutation of Hegel’s philosophy therefore contains premises from the originalausgabe, whereas a weak refutation of Hegel’s philosophy contains premises from the originalausgabe and from the non–authorized work, while a sophistical refutation contains no premise from the originalausgabe. Refutation of the Hegelian philosophy is inseparable from Hegel philology: Therefore, dialectical inference is inseparable from dialectical hermeneutics, as the notion of dialectical scientivity, — as the speculative logical and dialectical system of the pure Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism, in the realm of world history, in the collapse of European modernity and the rise of Global American civilization.
Of course, we perceive very clearly and distinctly, we lovers of the superior ruling class, that the genuine philosophy of Hegel does not divide Christians into schisms and sects, and thereby empower contemporary Machiavellism, as the Napoléonic and French Revolutionary delusion of right, especially in Brussels and Italy, but rather unites and uplifts world Christianity in the rise of Global civilization.
See also: Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse — Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Erste Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, Berlin, 1840, v–viii.
See also: Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse — Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Zweite Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, Berlin, 1843, v–viii.
See finally: “Michelet very clearly proves the Straussianism of Hegel, by citations from his lectures.”
Anonymous, “Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz: The Life of Hegel,” The Biblical Repertory and Princeton Review, 20.4(October, 1848): 585.
43. Knox, Ibidem, §352, 112.
See: “Die konkreten Ideen, die Völkergeister, haben ihre Wahrheit und Bestimmung in der konkreten Idee, wie sie die absolute Allgemeinheit ist, — dem Weltgeist, um dessen Thron sie als die Vollbringer seiner Verwirklichung, und als Zeugen und Zieraten seiner Herrlichkeit stehen. Indem er als Geist nur die Bewegung seiner Tätigkeit ist, sich absolut zu wissen, hiermit sein Bewußtsein von der Form der natürlichen Unmittelbarkeit zu befreien und zu sich selbst zu kommen, so sind die Prinzipien der Gestaltungen dieses Selbstbewußtseins in dem Gange seiner Befreiung.”
Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Zum Gebrauch für seine Vorlesungen, Berlin, 1821, §352, 349–350. See finally: Hegel, Ibidem, 1911, §352, 275.
That I have laid out some of the philosophical reasons for this doctrine in the third edition of another writing of mine, an outline of sorts, named Americanism, is of slight importance: That the teaching therein involves the sciences of economics and politics is of some interest, however, and therefore has a bearing upon the subject at hand, namely, as the developmental unification and coaxial integration of the American world. In that work I flatter myself as the first Hegelian philosopher ever to apply the Dialectic of Hegel to the Hegelian Dialectic: “Modern irrationalism, in order to validate pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism, squares the Lecture Notes and the great works published by Hegel in his lifetime. Pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism thus squares both Kant and Hegel in order to prove the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of Absolute Idealism is flawed. Irrationalism thus perverts the history of philosophy and modern Europe … Pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism is therefore the political and economic mask of modern European Raison d’État. One drawback will never be remedied in Hegel philology: The Lecture Notes are not authoritative and are therefore useless in the exact determination of the ultimate worth of genuine Hegelianism … In the 20th century upwards of 500 million human beings were slaughtered in the contagion of modern political and economic satanism, more than in all the periods of history combined: Many hundreds of millions more were utterly ruined and destroyed by the most barbaric slavery ever recorded in the world. This is the ultimate verdict of exact historiography and universal history. From whence comes the disease of modern unreason?”
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Americanism: The New Hegelian Orthodoxy, 3rd edition, San Francisco, California, 2016, 6–9.
44. Eduard Gans, “Additions to The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, Chicago, 1960, Addition 86 = §135,129–Addition 152 = §258, 141.
See: Eduard Gans, “Zusätze aus Hegels Vorlesungen, zusammengestellt,” Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Eduard Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, neu hrsg., von Georg Lasson, Herausgegeber, Leipzig, 1911, Zusätze 86 = §135, 318–Zusätze 152 = §258, 349: “Den Standpunkt der Kantischen Philosophie hervorhoben … Es ist der Gang Gottes in der Welt, daß der Staat ist.”
45. The following list of satanic ideas in which modern unreason, especially in 20th century world history, is served up on a new platter by inferior ruling classes is not exhaustive: Darwinism, phenomenology, positivism, phenomenalism, pragmatism, behaviorism, dialectical materialism, existentialism, analysis, physicalism, materialism, naturalism, realism, psycho–analysis and so forth, oftentimes set in stark contradistinction to Western philosophy pejoratively comprehended as Platonism, metaphysics, idealism, noologism, rationalism, spiritualism, dialectics, ideology, historicism, essentialism, theology, absolutism and so on …
46. See: “All things that exist being particulars … every man’s reasoning and knowledge is only about the ideas existing in his own mind.”
John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, New Edition, 2 vols., New York, 1824, 381/I–203/II.
Thus, the world does not exist, according to John Locke, while the universe is appearance and delusion.
See also: “Locke was heavily involved in the slave trade, both through his investments and through his administrative supervision of England’s burgeoning colonial activities … The attempt to reconcile Locke’s involvement in the slave trade with his reputation as a philosopher of liberal freedom has a long history, beginning shortly after the abolition of the slave trade … Locke’s readers are faced with the problem of how he could have been so intimately involved in promoting an activity that he apparently knew to be unjustified … We are disturbed by the ease with which some commentators excuse Locke of racism or minimize its significance … to advocate, administer, and profit from a specifically racialized form of slavery is clear evidence of [Locke’s] racism, if the word is to have any meaning at all.”
Robert Bernasconi and Anika Maaza Mann, “The Contradictions of Racism: Locke, Slavery, and the Two Treatises,” Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy, Andrew Valls, editor, Ithaca/London, 2005, 89–89–90–91–91.
See finally Cartesius: “Ego cogito, ergo sum, sive existo … ea enim est natura nostrae mentis, ut generales propostiones ex particularium cognitione efformet.”
Cartesius, “Secundæ Responsiones,” Œuvres de Descartes: Meditationes de Prima Philosophia, vol. 7, Charles Adam & Paul Tannery, éditeurs, Paris, 1904, 140–141.
How very clear and distinct are the ideas of Cartesius, coming from his very own hand, although his best translators are also clear and distinct, but less clear and less distinct than the very words of Cartesius himself, as found in his very greatest works, since his Latin is now a dead language, while his modern interpreters fail to elucidate the rational foundations of their sophistical critiques.
47. See: “[Roman Law] was the law of the continent of Europe wherever based on the civil law, till the adoption and spread of the Code Napoléon, first among the Latin races, and more recently among the nations of central and northern Europe. The French Code … would thus seem to have swept away at once the entire doctrine dependent upon the Roman system.”
Judah Philip Benjamin, A Treatise on the Law of Sale of Personal Property: With References to the American Decisions and to the French Code and Civil Law, London, 1868, 299.
See: “Napoléon Bonaparte, who uplifted himself, by which means no one has ever determined, to the heights of conceptual power in his knowledge of the greatest problems of jurisprudence and legislation, often participated in the deliberations of the Judicial Council. Napoléon’s great genius, his profound method and penetrating insight, always astonished the members of the judiciary.”
Frédéric Mourlon, Répétitions écrites sur le code civil contenant l’exposé des principes généraux leurs motifs et la solution des questions théoriques, 11e édition, revue et mise au courant par Charles Demangeat, Tome premier, Paris, 1880, 24. [1846] “Napoléon, qui s’est élevé, on ne sait comment, jusqu’à l’intelligence des problèmes les plus ardus du droit et de la législation, pris souvent part aux discussions du Conseil. Il y déploya toujours une clarté, une méthode, et quelquefois une profondeur de vues, qui furent pour tout le monde un sujet d’étonnement.”
See also: “It is the soldier who founds a republic and it is the soldier who maintains it.”
Napoléon Bonaparte in Herbert Albert Laurens Fisher, Bonapartism: Six Lectures Delivered in the University of London, Oxford, 1908, 21. See: “There is no mystery about the origins of Bonapartism. It is the child of Napoléon Bonaparte and the French Revolution … the strong executive founded upon the plebiscite which was to be the pillar of Bonapartism; and [Napoléon] had come to the conclusion that legislative assemblies should be merely supervisory, that they should have no power to change the constitution or to interfere with the executive … This is not the place for a detailed examination of the principles of Napoléonic law. It is well, however, to notice that the civil code alone was drawn up during the Consulate, that it is nearer both in time and spirit to the revolutionary law than are the codes which were compiled in a more perfunctory manner under the darker shadows of imperial despotism … in the codes, in the common system of administration, the foundations of a modern Italy were laid. And here the memory of Napoléon was not easily forgotten … The French nation, being consulted for the third time, for the third time by an overwhelming majority ratified its belief in Bonapartism … The guiding principle of Bonapartism was autocracy founded on popular consent, safeguarding social order and social equality.”
Fisher, Ibidem, 7–22–39–55–87–120.
See also: “We propose a comparison between the doctrine of Machiavelli, as it emerges from the Prince, and the doctrine of absolutism, which we shall endeavor to discern, not from one or another of the theorists who were its champions, but from all of them … the absolutist doctrines, in their application, lead rulers to the same results as the doctrines of Machiavelli … Machiavellism and absolutism are derived from analogous historical situations. This is the first essential point of our parallel. The historical situation inspires Machiavelli with the idea of the legitimacy of every means aimed at the achievement of public interest and the salvation of the State … those who were able to study Napoléon Bonaparte very closely tell us that he was a very powerful ruler who saw the spilling of blood [sang des hommes répandu] as perhaps the greatest remedy of political medicine … The Prince of Machiavelli and the doctrines of absolutism were born of the same sentiment of profound patriotism, at times and in countries where a powerful sovereign was necessary to put an end to the disorder and turmoil of the day, the causes of national distress … Machiavelli reveals himself as an immoral patriot who wants to save the State, even though his conception of government appears as a policy that is respectful of political freedoms and that is aimed at the happiness of the people.”
Louis Couzinet, “Le Prince” de Machiavel et la théorie de l’absolutisme, Paris, 1910, xix–xxi–xxvii–136–349–352: “Nous nous proposons un rapprochement, une comparaison, entre la doctrine de Machiavel, telle qu’elle ressort du Prince, et la doctrine de l’absolutisme, que nous essayerons de dégager, non pas de tel ou tel des théoriciens qui en furent les champions; mais de l’ensemble de ces théoriciens … les doctrines absolutistes, dans leur application, conduisent les princes aux mêmes résultats que les doctrines de Machiavel … Machiavélisme et absolutisme sont issus de situations historiques analogues. C’est là un premier point essentiel de notre parallèle. Cette situation inspire à Machiavel l’idée de la légitimité de tous les moyens destinés à atteindre un but d’intérêt public et à réaliser le salut de l’État … Tous ceux qui ont pu étudier Napoléon l de près, nous disent qu’il y avait en lui le Napoléon homme d’État, qui voyait dans le sang des hommes répandu un des grands remèdes de la médecine politique … Le Prince de Machiavel et les doctrines de l’absolutisme sont nés d’un même sentiment profond de patriotisme, à des époques et dans des pays où un souverain puissant était nécessaire pour faire cesser, sous sa domination, les désordres et la désunion, causes de la détresse nationale … Machiavel nous apparaît comme un patriote sans scrupule lorsqu’il s’agit de sauver l’État. Dans sa conception du gouvernement il se révèle à nous comme un politique soucieux du bonheur du peuple et respectueux de sa liberté.”
See finally: Abbé Aimé Guillon de Montléon (1758–1842), Machiavel commenté par Napoléon Bonaparte, manuscrit trouvé dans la carrosse de Bonaparte, après la bataille de Mont–Saint–Jean, le 15 février 1815, Paris,1816.
48. Anonymous, “Karl Rosenkranz: The Life of Hegel,” The Biblical Repertory and Princeton Review, 20.4(October, 1848): 575–586.
See: “[Hegel’s] legacy was quickly dispersed into … the service of orthodox Protestant theology.”
George Di Giovanni, “The New Spinozism,” The Edinburgh Critical History of Nineteenth–Century Philosophy, Alison Stone, editor and Howard Caygill and David Webb, general editors, Edinburgh, 2011, 27.
See also: “What Luther initiated as faith in feeling and in the witness of the spirit, is precisely what spirit, since become more mature, has striven to apprehend in the concept in order to free and so to find itself in the world as it exists today … Mind is here pressed back upon itself in the extreme of its absolute negativity. This is the absolute turning point; mind rises out of this situation and grasps the infinite positivity of this its inward character, i.e., it grasps the principle of the unity of the divine nature and the human, the reconciliation of objective truth and freedom as the truth and freedom appearing within self–consciousness and subjectivity, a reconciliation with the fulfilment of which the principle of the north, the principle of the Germanic peoples, has been entrusted.”
Hegel, Great Books of the Western World, vol. 46, Chicago, 1960, Preface–§358, 7–113.
See also: “Was Luther als Glauben im Gefühl und im Zeugnis des Geistes begonnen, es ist dasselbe, was der weiterhin gereifte Geist im Begriffe zu fassen, und so in der Gegenwart sich zu befreien, und dadurch in ihr sich zu finden bestrebt ist … erfaßt der in sich zurückgedrängte Geist in dem Extreme seiner absoluten Negativität, dem an und für sich seienden Wendepunkt, die unendliche Positivität dieses seines Innern, das Prinzip der Einheit der göttlichen und menschlichen Natur, die Versöhnung als der innerhalb des Selbstbewußtseins und der Subjektivität erschienenen objektiven Wahrheit und Freiheit, welche dem nordischen Prinzip der germanischen Völker zu vollführen übertragen wird.”
Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Zum Gebrauch für seine Vorlesungen, Berlin, 1821, Vorrede–§358, xxiii–353. See finally: Hegel, Philosophische Bibliothek: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Band 124, Leipzig, 1911, Vorrede–§358, 16–278.
See finally: “The persistence of the idealist tradition in Germany long after Hegel’s death … was continued not only by minor figures in very obscure places, but by major figures in very prominent ones … the idealistic tradition in Germany came to an end not with cholera in 1832 but with a cold in 1881 …[German Idealism] went back to Leibniz and Kant, and … was carried forward by Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel … with further research and reflection the classification could be refined in all kinds of ways … one of the least appealing aspects of the idealist tradition from Kant down to Hegel is its notorious obscurity, which derives not least from its esoteric vocabulary and technical jargon. To understand idealist texts, it seems, one needs to be gifted with intellectual intuitions, or one has to cultivate a special technique of reasoning (the dialectic).”
Frederick C. Beiser, The Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg & Lotze, Oxford, 2014, 1–4. [2013]
Modern irrationalists in Britain like Frederick Beiser place Kant and Hegel together as German Idealists in their so–called histories of philosophy without drawing the rational distinction between sophistical and philosophical idealism, — which is also the division between the rise of Globalism and decline of modernity in world history:
“The Kantian philosophy thus serves as a cushion for intellectual indolence which soothes itself with the conviction that everything is already proved and settled.”
Hegel, “Introduction: General Division of Logic,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator & Forward by John Niemeyer Findlay, New York, 1976, 62. [1969]
See: Hegel, “Einleitung: Allgemeine Eintheilung der Logik,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Zweite Ausgabe, Stuttgart und Tübingen, 1832, 30. [1812]
See also: Hegel, “Einleitung,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Nürnberg, 1812, i–xxvii.
Modern sophists are corrupt (impure) Hegelians and their historiography is therefore defective. As such they aim to downplay the rise of world civilization and the collapse of European modernity, and thereby create political and economic resistance to Globalism among the British intelligentsia, as a breathing space for the backwards cartels, outdated monopolies and corrupt trusts of their masters, the inferior ruling classes. Sophists like Frederick Beiser will deny that they are the same old pseudo–Hegelians and anti–Hegelians of yesterday precisely because they are not what they name “idealists.” Modern sophists thus use what they term the “idealist tradition” as a mask, to hide their own irrationalism, especially in the arena of politics and economics: What is this but the modern technique of the imbecile ruling classes and their flabby minds? They follow in the footsteps of the Great Sophist himself:
“The United States … imposes intolerable regimes on Asian, Latin American, and Middle East countries, and economically exploits the great majority of mankind who live at below–subsistence level to support American profit … The American government pursues a policy of genocide.”
Bertrand Russell (1963) in Harvey Arthur DeWeerd, Lord Russell’s War Crimes Tribunal, Santa Monica, 1967, 4.
These same sophists wish (or pretend to wish) to bring back Eurocentricism and make the European Union into the 21st century bastion of the Napoléonic and French revolutionary conception of right. Philosophers of today, whose minds are liberated by the rise of Global freedom of thought, will notice that while our present day pseudo–Hegelians and anti–Hegelians are not “idealists” (according to their own esoteric terminology) they are nevertheless modern irrationalists all the same: Their subjectivism, relativism and irrationalism comes from the same old delusion of Kant albeit served up on a new platter. For this reason the phantasms of the modern sophists evaporate before the corrosive onslaught of Americanism: The superior ruling classes of Europe have been profoundly influenced by Washington and American political and economic rationality in the world of today.
See: “[Frederick Beiser] claims that, beginning with Schelling and Hegel, German philosophy reverted to the sort of ‘speculative metaphysics’ that Kant’s Critical Philosophy had attempted to put aside once and for all.”
David A. Duquette, editor, Hegel’s History of Philosophy: New Interpretations, Albany, New York, State University of New York Press, 2003, 212.
See: “One of the most striking and characteristic features of Hegel’s thought is that it historicizes [relativizes] philosophy … [Hegel] accepts Kant’s critical teaching that metaphysics is not possible as speculation about a realm of transcendent entities, and that it is possible only if it does not transcend the limits of possible experience … [Hegel] explains the existence of evil by showing it to be necessary for the realization of the end of history … [the] self–critical dimension of Hegel’s historicism was his completion of Kant’s project for a critique of pure reason. Like Kant, Hegel believed that philosophy should become self–critical … Hegel’s historicism is perhaps most explicit in his Lectures on the History of Philosophy.”
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, “Hegel’s Historicism,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, Cambridge, 1993, 270–271–271–272–273.
Hegel explains the existence of evil by showing it to be necessary for the realization of the end of history? But which Hegel is this, the genuine Hegel of the Pure Hegelianism of the Originalausgabe or the Hegel of impure Hegelianism, the bastion of pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism? The rational conception of the necessity and realization of the end of existence in the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism is mortally opposed to the Kantio–Hegelian phantasms of Frederick Beiser and the modern irrationalists:
“Reflective understanding took possession of philosophy … this turn taken by cognition, which appears as a loss and retrograde step, is based on something more profound on which rests the elevation of reason into the loftier spirit of modern philosophy. The basis of that universally held conception is, namely, to be sought in the insight into the necessary conflict of the determinations of the understanding with themselves. The reflection already referred to is this, to transcend the concrete immediate object and to determine it and separate it. But equally it must transcend these its separating determinations and straightway connect them. It is at the stage of this connecting of the determinations that their conflict emerges. This connecting activity of reflection belongs in itself to reason and the rising above those determinations which attains to an insight into their conflict is the great negative step towards the true Notion of reason. But the insight, when not thorough–going, commits the mistake of thinking that it is reason which is in contradiction with itself; it does not recognize that the contradiction is precisely the rising of reason above the limitations of the understanding and the resolving of them. Cognition, instead of taking from this stage the final step into the heights, has fled from the unsatisfactoriness of the categories of the understanding to sensuous existence, imagining that in this it possesses what is solid and self–consistent. But on the other hand, since this knowledge is self–confessedly knowledge only of appearances, the unsatisfactoriness of the latter is admitted, but at the same time presupposed: As much as to say that admittedly, we have no proper knowledge of things–in–themselves but we do have a proper knowledge of them within the sphere of appearances, as if, so to speak, only the kind of objects were different, and one kind, namely things–in–themselves, did not fall within the scope of our knowledge but the other kind did, phenomena did.”
Hegel, “Introduction: General Notion of Logic,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator & Forward by John Niemeyer Findlay, New York, 1976, 46–46. [1969]
See: Hegel, “Einleitung,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Nürnberg, 1812, v–vii.
As the general notion of logic, cognition transcends the concrete immediate object and determines and separates it, and equally transcends its separating determinations and straightway connects them. At the stage of this connecting of the determinations conflict emerges. This connecting activity of reflection belongs in itself to reason, while the rising above those determinations is the insight into their conflict, which is the great negative step towards the true Notion of reason. The insight when not thorough–going commits the mistake of thinking that it is reason which is in contradiction with itself; it does not recognize that the contradiction is precisely the rising of reason above the limitations of the understanding and the resolving of them. Because of his Kantio–Hegelianism, Frederick Beiser does not therefore understand that the genuine Hegel of Pure Hegelianism does not explain the existence of evil by showing it to be necessary for the realization of the end of history. Reason, in the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism, rises above the limitations of the understanding and resolves them as the true Notion, within the general conception of logic. Shall we therefore hold that the realm of philosophy and world history is beyond the self–determination of reason and the general conception of logic in the speculative logical and dialectical system of the genuine Hegel’s philosophical science of absolute idealism? We most certainly shall not espouse the lost cause of Kantio–Hegelianism: We shall meticulously avoid the camp of pseudo–Hegelianism and anti–Hegelianism, which is condemned to rot upon the dunghill of history.
See: “Perhaps some commentators think that the non– or anti– or a–metaphysical character of Hegel’s ‘absolute idealism’ (as he himself calls it) can be proven by consistently translating it into twentieth–century language that they deem free from metaphysical assumptions. If such a transposition succeeded without losing essential elements of Hegel’s texts, their account would perhaps corroborate their thesis. If, on the contrary, Hegel’s thought cannot be captured in this transposition, their commentaries are obviously partial or unilateral. Hegel himself would call them untrue. If a partial reading is presented as equivalent to the whole, it is even false. But if the logic, as the heart of Hegel’s thinking, is metaphysical, why are certain commentators so attracted to it that they spend considerable energy reshaping it into their own image?”
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “Introduction,” Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, Dordrecht, 2001, 1–52, 6.
The mortal opposition of Pure Hegelianism to modern irrationalism is found in the American Idealism of Washington and the rise of Global political and economic rationality in the world of today.
49. In the last decade of his life, the old Hegel published nothing really new, apart from increasing the size of the Encyclopedia, and he made no departure from the system of Pure Hegelianism. Hegel’s intellectual powers waned in the political and theological strife of Berlin:
“The writer must content himself with what he has been allowed to achieve under the pressure of circumstances, the unavoidable waste caused by the extent and many–sidedness of the interests of the time, and the haunting doubt whether, amid the loud clamor of the day and the deafening babble of opinion … there is left any room for sympathy with the passionless stillness of a science of pure thought.”
Hegel (1831) in Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, “Biographical Note: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, 1770–1831,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator, vol. 46, Chicago, 1960, v–vi.
Old Hegel complains that “he must content himself with what he has been allowed to achieve under the pressure of circumstances, the unavoidable waste caused by the extent and many–sidedness of the interests of the time,” and he is haunted by the “doubt whether, amid the loud clamor of the day and the deafening babble of opinion … there is left any room for sympathy with the passionless stillness of a science of pure thought.”
The “deafening babble of opinion” is the work of the sophists, the Kantian school at Berlin, the followers of Fichte. The “loud clamor of the day” is the religious and political strife resultant from the French revolution and Napoléon. The “pressure of circumstances” is Hegel’s political and administrative work at the university, while the “unavoidable waste caused by the extent and many–sidedness of the interests of the time” is Hegel’s neglect of intense intellectual work under the burdens of academic lectures. The “haunting doubt whether … there is left any room for sympathy with the passionless stillness of a science of pure thought,” are the words of an intellectual leader whose school is beginning to exhibit the first symptoms of the coming upheaval.
These words of the old Hegel at the height of his academic and political power, exhausted and haunted by doubt in the twilight of his intellectual life, are lifted from the 1831 preface to the second edition of the Great Logic (Zweite Ausgabe, Stuttgart & Tübingen, Cotta, 1832), which was published in the very influential Berlin editions of 1833 and 1841, after the death of Hegel, so that the true significance of their meaning is obscured by the many modifications, additions and notes of Hegel’s students and editors: The genuine Hegelian philosophy of the Originalausgabe contains the diamond purity of Hegelianism, — the rational germ of Hegel’s “freshness and power.”
See: “One man has understood me, and even he has not.”
Hegel in William Wallace, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 11th edition, vol. 13, New York, 1911, 200–207, 204.
See: “It is a mistake to regard his [Hegel’s] philosophy as nothing more than the logical outcome of Kant’s system. The influence of Greek philosophy on Hegel, particularly of Plato and Aristotle, must not be overlooked. Indeed, it is not difficult to defend the thesis that the essentials of Hegel’s philosophy are to be found in Plato and Aristotle and that all that he did was to make a new synthesis of them with such modifications as modern knowledge required. The beginning, for example, of his logic, all that he says about being and nothing, will be found almost in identical terms in Plato’s Parmenides.”
Hiralal Haldar, Neo–Hegelianism, London, 1927, 10.
See also: “It is the Transcendental Deduction that has played the most important part in the arguments of the English Kantio–Hegelians.”
Andrew Seth Pringle–Pattison in Hiralal Haldar, Essays in Philosophy, Calcutta, 1920, 6.
See also: “The problem as to whether or not and to what extent Hegel succeeded in overcoming Kant’s ‘thing–in–itself’ is a separate question. At any rate, this was his aim. In a metaphysics of the Absolute Spirit, realities beyond the realm of knowledge, in so far as the ‘thing–in–itself’ represents such realities, cannot exist.”
Richard Hoenigswald, “Philosophy of Hegelianism,” Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought, Dagobert David Runes, editor, New York, 1947, 270.
See finally: “Hegel’s presence in twentieth–century philosophy is overwhelming … Was Hegel too complicated, or too much of a Janus, to be understood in a non–unilateral, dialectical, rational way?”
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “Introduction,” Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, Dordrecht, 2001, 1–49.
BIBLIOGRAPHY OF WORKS CITED
Anonymous, “Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz: The Life of Hegel,” The Biblical Repertory and Princeton Review, 20.4(October, 1848): 561–591.
Anonymous, “Social Net Not Part of Trade Talks: Reisman,” The Montreal Gazette, 15 May 1986, A9.
Beiser, Frederick C., editor, “Hegel’s Historicism,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 270–300.
Bélanger, Jules, Jean–Louis Lévesque: La montée d’un Gaspésien aux sommets des affaires, (Saint–Laurent: Fides, 1996).
Benjamin, Judah Philip, A Treatise on the Law of Sale of Personal Property: With References to the American Decisions and to the French Code and Civil Law, (London: Henry Sweet, 1868).
Bernasconi, Robert and Anika Maaza Mann, “The Contradictions of Racism: Locke, Slavery, and the Two Treatises,” Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy, Andrew Valls, editor, (Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press, 2005), 89–107.
Brown, Robert F., translator and editor, “Editorial Introduction: 1. Background Issues,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures (Together with an Introduction by Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert), (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2014), 1–4.
Burbidge, John W., “Eduard Gans (1798–1839),” Historical Dictionary of Hegelian Philosophy, (Lanham, Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, 2008), 80.
Burdon, Richard (Viscount Haldane), “Hegel,” The Contemporary Review, 67(February, 1895): 232–245.
Burdon, Richard (Viscount Haldane), “Introductory Preface,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, vol. 1, By Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Walter Henry Johnston and Leslie Graham Struthers, translators, (London: Cambridge University Press, 1929), 7–15.
Cartesius, Renatus, “Secundæ Responsiones,” Œuvres de Descartes: Meditationes de Prima Philosophia, vol. 7, Charles Adam & Paul Tannery, éditeurs, (Paris: Léopold Cerf, 1904), 128–159.
Chomsky, Noam, Year 501: The Conquest Continues, (Montréal/New York: Black Rose Books, 1993).
Clemenceau, George, “Appendice,” De la Génération des Éléments anatomiques, (Paris: Chez J.–B. Baillière et Fils, Libraires de l’Académie Impériale de Médecine, 1865), 185–222.
Clemenceau, George, “Appendice,” Notions d’anatomie et de physiologie: De la Génération des Éléments anatomiques, Charles Robin, Introduction, (Paris: Librairie Germer Baillière, 1867), 227–281.
Clemenceau, Georges, Vers la réparation, (Paris: P.–V. Stock, Éditeur, 1899).
Clemenceau, Georges, La France devant l’Allemagne, (Paris: Librairie Payot & Cie, 1918).
Courtois, Stéphane, editor & contributor, “The Crimes of Communism,” The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression, Karel Bartošek, Sylvain Boulouque, Pascal Fontaine, Rémi Kauffer, Martin Malia, Jean–Louis Margolin, Andrzej Paczkowski, Jean–Louis Panné, Pierre Rigoulot, Yves Santamaria & Nicolas Werth, contributors, Jonathan Murphy & Mark Kramer (consulting editor), translators, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1999), 1–31.
Courtois, Stéphane, editor & contributor, “Why?” The Black Book of Communism: Crimes, Terror, Repression, Karel Bartošek, Sylvain Boulouque, Pascal Fontaine, Rémi Kauffer, Martin Malia, Jean–Louis Margolin, Andrzej Paczkowski, Jean–Louis Panné, Pierre Rigoulot, Yves Santamaria & Nicolas Werth, contributors, Jonathan Murphy & Mark Kramer, translators, Mark Kramer, consulting editor, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1999), 727–757.
Couzinet, Louis, “Le Prince” de Machiavel et la théorie de l’absolutisme, (Paris: Librairie Nouvelle de Droit et de Jurisprudence, Arthur Rousseau, Éditeur, 1910).
Croce, Benedetto, What Is Living and What Is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel, 3rd edition, Douglas Ainslie, translator, (London: Macmillan, 1915). [1906]
De Beauvoir, Simone et Madeleine Gobeil, “Entrevue avec Simone de Beauvoir,” Cité Libre: Nouvelle série, 16(15).69(août–septembre, 1964): 30–31.
Dettling, Christopher Richard Wade, Americanism: The New Hegelian Orthodoxy, 3rd edition, (San Francisco, California: The Internet Archive, 2016).
Dettling, Christopher Richard Wade, Americanism: Stronghold of Hegel, Holograph Manuscript, Montreal/Vancouver, 2013.
DeWeerd, Harvey Arthur, Lord Russell’s War Crimes Tribunal, (Santa Monica: The RAND Corporation, 1967).
Dewey, John, “Kant and Philosophic Method,” Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 18(1 April, 1884): 162–174.
Dottori, Riccardo, A Century of Philosophy: Hans–Georg Gadamer in Conversation With Riccardo Dottori, Rod Coltman and Sigrid Koepke, translators, (New York: Continuum, 2006). [2000]
Erdmann, Johann Eduard, A History of Philosophy: German Philosophy Since Hegel, 4th German edition, vol. 3, Williston Samuel Hough, editor, (London: Swann Sonnenschein & Company,1899).
Fisher, Herbert Albert Laurens, Bonapartism: Six Lectures Delivered in the University of London, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1908).
Foster, Michael Beresford, The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel, (New York: Russell and Russell, 1965). [1935]
Gadamer, Hans–Georg, Hegel’s Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, translated with an introduction by P. Christopher Smith, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1976). [1971]
Gans, Eduard, “Additions to The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1960), Addition 1–Addition 194, 115–150. [Lasson, 2nd edition, 1921]
Gans, Eduard, “Zusätze aus Hegels Vorlesungen, zusammengestellt,” Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Eduard Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, neu hrsg., von Georg Lasson, Herausgegeber, [=Hegels sämtliche Werke, Band VI], (Leipzig: Verlag von Felix Meiner, 1911), Zusätze 1–Zusätze 194, 281–371.
Gethmann–Siefert, Annemarie, “Introduction: The Shape and Influence of Hegel’s Aesthetics,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures, Robert F. Brown, editor and translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2014), 7–176.
Di Giovanni, George, “The New Spinozism,” The Edinburgh Critical History of Nineteenth–Century Philosophy, Alison Stone, editor and Howard Caygill and David Webb, general editors, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2011), 13–28.
Gobeil, Madeleine et Simone de Beauvoir, “Entrevue avec Simone de Beauvoir,” Cité Libre: Nouvelle série, 16(15).69(août–septembre, 1964): 30–31.
Guillon de Montléon, Aimé, Machiavel commenté par Napoléon Bonaparte, manuscrit trouvé dans la carrosse de Bonaparte, après la bataille de Mont–Saint–Jean, le 15 février 1815, (Paris: Nicolle, 1816).
Haldar, Hiralal, Neo–Hegelianism, (London: Heath Cranton, Ltd., 1927).
Haldar, Hiralal, Essays in Philosophy, (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1920).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich and Eduard Gans, “The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica Inc., 1960), vii–150. [Lasson, 2nd edition, 1921]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, “The Philosophy of Right,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1960), vii–114. [Lasson, 2nd edition, 1921]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, “Introduction: General Notion of Logic,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator & Forward by John Niemeyer Findlay, (New York: The Humanities Press, 1976), 43–59. [1969]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, “Introduction: General Division of Logic,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator & Forward by John Niemeyer Findlay, (New York: The Humanities Press, 1976), 59–64. [1969]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, “Einleitung,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objective Logik, Erster Band, (Nürnberg: Johann Leonhard Schrag, 1812), i–xxvii.
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Zum Gebrauch für seine Vorlesungen, (Berlin: Nicolaische Buchhandlung, 1821).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, “Einleitung: Allgemeine Eintheilung der Logik,” Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Zweite Ausgabe, (Stuttgart und Tübingen: J.F. Cotta’schen Buchhandlung, 1832), 26–34. [1812]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Philosophische Bibliothek: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit den von Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Neu herausgegeben von Georg Lasson, Band 124, (Leipzig: Verlag von Felix Meiner, 1911).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Philosophische Bibliothek: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit Hegels eigenhändigen Randbemerkungen in seinem Handexemplar der Rechtsphilosophie, Vierte Auflage, Band 124a, Johannes Hoffmeister, Herausgegeber, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag 1967). [1955]
Hegel, “Die Verfassung Deutschlands,” Samtliche Werke: Schriften zur Politik und Rechtsphilosophie, Unter Mitwirkung von Dr. Otto Weiß, Hrsg., Georg Lasson, Band VII (Der Philosophischen Bibliothek, Band 144), (Leipzig: Felix Meiner, 1913), 1–149.
Heine, Heinrich, Religion and Philosophy in Germany: A Fragment, John Snodgrass, translator & Ludwig Marcuse, editor, introduction, (Beacon Hill, Boston: Beacon Press, 1959), xiv. [1834]
Henning, Leopold Dorotheus von, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse — Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Erste Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1840), v–viii.
Henning, Leopold Dorotheus von, Hrsg., “Vorwort des Herausgebers,” Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse — Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Zweite Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1843), v–viii.
Hoenigswald, Richard, “Philosophy of Hegelianism,” Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought, Dagobert David Runes, editor, (New York: Philosophical Library, 1947), 267–291.
Hutchins, Robert Maynard, editor, “Biographical Note: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, 1770–1831,” Great Books of the Western World: Hegel, vol. 46, Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator, (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1960), v–vi.
Kant, Immanuel, “The Critique of Pure Reason,” Great Books of the Western World: Kant, vol. 42, John Miller Dow Meiklejohn, translator & Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica Inc., 1960), vii–250.
Kant, Immanuel, Kant’s Principles of Politics Including His Essay on Perpetual Peace: A Contribution to Political Science, William Hastie, translator & editor, (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1891).
Kant, Immanuel, Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: A Commemoration of the Centenary of Its First Publication, 2 vols., Friedrich Maximilian Müller, translator, (London: Macmillan, 1881).
Knox, Thomas Malcolm, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: William Benton, 1967), 298–303.
Kripke, Saul Aron, “Naming and Necessity: Lecture I, 20 January 1970,” Semantics of Natural Language (Synthese Library), № 40, Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, editors, (Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, 1972), 253–355.
Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, New Edition, 2 vols., (New York: Valentine Seaman, 1824). [1690]
Longuenesse, Béatrice, Hegel et la critique de la métaphysique: Étude sur la doctrine de l’essence, (Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1981).
Mach, Ernst, “Author’s Preface to the Seventh German Edition,” The Science of Mechanics: A Critical and Historical Account of Its Development, Supplement to the Third English Edition Containing the Author’s Additions to the Seventh German Edition, Philip Edward Bertrand Jourdain, translator and annotator, (Chicago and London: The Open Court Publishing Company, 1915), ix–xii. [1912]
Mach, Ernst, Die Mechanik in ihrer Enwickelung: Historisch–Kritisch Dargestellt, Siebente verbesserte und vermehrte Auflage, (Leipzig: F.A. Brockhaus, 1912).
Machiavelli, Niccolò di Bernardo dei, The Prince, Luigi Ricci, translator, (Oxford: Humphrey Milford, 1921).
Manchester, William, The Last Lion: Winston Spencer Churchill: Alone, 1932–1940, vol. 2, (Boston: Little, Brown & Company, 1988).
Massie, Robert Kinloch, Nicholas and Alexandra, (New York: Atheneum, 1967).
McGrath, Sean J. and Joseph Carew, editors, “Introduction: What Remains of German Idealism?” Rethinking German Idealism, Joseph Carew, Wes Furlotte, Jean–Christophe Goddard, Adrian Johnston, Cem Kömürcü, Sean J. McGrath, Constantin Rauer, Alexander Schnell, F. Scott Scribner, Devin Zane Shaw, Konrad Utz, Jason M. Wirth, contributors, (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016), 1–19.
Melamed, Yitzhak Y. and Peter Thielke, “Hegelianism,” New Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Game Theory to Lysenkoism, vol. 3, Maryanne Cline Horowitz, editor in chief, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 2005), 975–977.
Morell, John Daniel, Historical and Critical View of the Speculative Philosophy of Europe in the Nineteenth Century, 2nd edition, 1 volume edition, (New York: Robert Carter, 1848). [1846]
Mourlon, Frédéric, Répétitions écrites sur le code civil contenant l’exposé des principes généraux leurs motifs et la solution des questions théoriques, 11e édition, revue et mise au courant par Charles Demangeat, Tome premier, (Paris: Garniers Frères, Libraires–Éditeurs, 1880). [1846]
Peperzak, Adriaan Theodoor Basilius, Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, (Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media, B.V., 2001).
Peperzak, Adriaan Theodoor Basilius, “Introduction,” Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, (Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media, B.V., 2001), 1–52.
Philpot, Robin, “Paul Desmarais: un bilan s’impose,” Le Devoir, 12 octobre 2013.
Pöggeler, Otto, “Editorial Introduction,” Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: The First Philosophy of Right, Heidelberg 1817–1818, With Additions From the Lectures of 1818–1819, G.W.F. Hegel & Peter Wannenmann; J. Michael Stewart & Peter C. Hodgson, editors and translators; Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Friedrich Hogemann, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme, Hans Christian Lucas, Kurt Rainer Meist & Hans Josef Schneider, Staff of the Hegel Archives editors, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 1–43. [1983 & 1995]
Russell, Bertrand, German Social Democracy: Six Lectures, With an Appendix on Social Democracy and the Woman Question in Germany by Alys Russell, (London and New York: Longmans, Green and Company, 1896).
Russell, Bertrand Arthur William, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” History of Western Philosophy and its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day, (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1947), 757–773. [1946]
Sandars, Thomas Collett, “Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” Oxford Essays, Contributed by Members of the University, (London: John W. Parker and Son, 1855), 213–250.
Schiller, Ferdinand Canning Scott, Plato or Protagoras? Being a Critical Examination of the Protagoras Speech in the Theaetetus with Some Remarks Upon Error, (Oxford: Basil H. Blackwell, 1908).
Schiller, Ferdinand Canning Scott, Studies in Humanism, (London: Macmillan, 1907).
Spiegelberg, Herbert, The Phenomenological Movement: A Historical Introduction, 2 vols., (Dordrecht: Springer, 1960).
Stalin, Joseph, “Anarchism or Socialism?” Works: 1901–1907, vol. 1, (Moscow: Foreign Language Publishing House, 1954), 279–372.
St. Aubyn, Giles, Edward VII: Prince and King, (New York: Atheneum, 1979).
Stern, Robert, “Hegel, British Idealism, and the Curious Case of the Concrete Universal,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15.1(2007): 115–153.
Wallace, William, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 11th edition, vol. 13, (New York: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1911), 200–207.
Wallace, William, Kant, (Edinburgh: William Blackwood & Sons, 1911).
HEGEL’S ORIGINALAUSGABE 1807–1821
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, System der Wissenschaft: Phänomenologie des Geistes, Erster Theil, (Bamberg und Würzburg: Joseph Anton Goebhardt, 1807).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, (Nürnberg: Johann Leonhard Schrag, 1812).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik―Die Lehre vom Wesen, Erster Band, Zweites Buch, (Nürnberg: Johann Leonhard Schrag, 1813).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Wissenschaft der Logik: Die subjektive Logik―oder Lehre vom Begriff, Zweiter Band, (Nürnberg: Johann Leonhard Schrag, 1816).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, zum Gebrauch seiner Vorlesungen, (Heidelberg: August Osswald’s Universitätsbuchhandlung, 1817).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, zum Gebrauch fur seine Vorlesungen, (Berlin: Nicolaischen Buchhandlung, 1821).
HEGEL BIBLIOGRAPHY: ORIGINALAUSGABE 1827–1832 (ZWEITE & DRITTE AUSGABE)
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, zum Gebrauch seiner Vorlesungen, Zweite Ausgabe, (Heidelberg: Druck und Verlag von August Osswald, 1827). [1817]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse, zum Gebrauch seiner Vorlesungen, Dritte Ausgabe, (Heidelberg: Verwaltung des Oswald’schen Verlags (C.F. Winter), 1830). [1817 & 1827]
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Wissenschaft der Logik: Die objektive Logik, Erster Band, Zweite Ausgabe, (Stuttgart und Tübingen: J.F. Cotta’schen Buchhandlung, 1832). [1812]
HEGEL BIBLIOGRAPHY: 1832–1845 BERLIN WERKE (ERSTE AUFLAGE)
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Philosophische Abhandlungen: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erste Auflage, Erster (1) Band, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1832).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Phänomenologie des Geistes: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erste Auflage, Zweiter (2) Band, Johann Schulze, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1832).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Wissenschaft der Logik―Die objektive Logik―Die Lehre vom Seyn: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Erste Abtheilung, Erste Auflage, Dritter (3) Band, Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1833).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Wissenschaft der Logik―Die objektive Logik―Die Lehre vom Wesen: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Zweite Abtheilung, Erste Auflage, Vierter (4) Band, Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1834).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Wissenschaft der Logik―Die subjektive Logik―Die Lehre vom Begriff: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Zweiter Theil, Erste Auflage, Fünfter (5) Band, Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1834).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse―Die Logik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erster Theil, Erste Auflage, Sechster (6) Band, Leopold Dorotheus von Henning, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1840).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse―Vorlesungen über die Naturphilosophie: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Zweiter Theil, Erste Auflage, Siebenter (7) Band, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1842).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse―Die Philosophie des Geistes: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Dritter Theil, Erste Auflage, Siebenter (7) Band, Ludwig Boumann, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1845).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erste Auflage, Achter (8) Band, Eduard Gans, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1833).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Geschichte: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erste Auflage, Neunter (9) Band, Eduard Gans, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1837).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Aesthetik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Erste Theil, Erste Abtheilung, (Erster Band), Erste Auflage, Zehnter (10) Band, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1835).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Aesthetik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Zweiter Theil, Zweite Abtheilung, (Zweiter Band), Erste Auflage, Zehnter (10) Band, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1838).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Aesthetik: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, Dritter Theil, Dritte Abtheilung, (Dritter Band), Erste Auflage, Zehnter (10) Band, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1838).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Erster Band), Erste Auflage, Elfter (11) Band, Philipp Konrad Marheinecke, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1832).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion, nebst einer Schrift uber die Beweise vom Daseyn Gottes: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Zweiter Band), Erste Auflage, Zwolfter (12) Band, Philipp Konrad Marheinecke, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1832).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Erster Band), Erste Auflage, Driezehnter (13) Band, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1833).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Zweiter Band), Erste Auflage, Vierzehnter (14) Band, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1833).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Dritter Band), Erste Auflage, Fünfzehnter (15) Band, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1836).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vermischte Schriften: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Erster Band), Erste Auflage, Sechzehnter (16) Band, Friedrich Förster & Ludwig Boumann, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1834).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Vermischte Schriften: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel’s Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: D. Ph. Marheineke, D. J. Schulze, D. Ed. Gans, D. Lp. v. Henning, D. H. Hotho, D. K. Michelet, D. F. Förster, (Zweiter Band), Erste Auflage, Siebenzehnter (17) Band, Friedrich Förster & Ludwig Boumann, Hrsg., (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot, 1835).
HEGEL BIBLIOGRAPHY: VORLESUNGEN AUSGEWÄHLTE NACHSCHRIFTEN UND MANUSKRIPTE 1983–2007
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (1): Vorlesungen über Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft Heidelberg 1817–1818, Mit Nachträgen aus der Vorlesung 1818–1819, ―Nachgeschrieben von Peter Wannenmann, Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Kurt Rainer Meist, Friedrich Hogemann, Hans Josef Schneider, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme & Hans Christian Lucas, Herausgegeben, Mit einer Einleitung von Otto Pöggeler, Band 1, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1983).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (2): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Kunst, Berlin 1823,―Nachgeschrieben von Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Hrsg., Band 2, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1998).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (3): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion, Teil 1, Einleitung, Der Begriff der Religion, Walter Jaeschke, Hrsg., Band 3, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1983).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (4): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion, Teil 2, Die bestimmte Religion, in zwei Bänden: Textband (a), Anhang (b), Mit einem Begriffs– Realien– und Personenverzeichnis zum Gesamtwerk, Walter Jaeschke, Hrsg., Band 4, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1985).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (5): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion, Teil 3, Die vollendete Religion, Walter Jaeschke, Hrsg., Band 5, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1984).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (6): Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, Teil 1, Einleitung in die Geschichte der Philosophie, Orientalische Philosophie, Pierre Garniron & Walter Jaeschke, Herausgegeben, Band 6, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1994).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (7): Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, Teil 2, Griechische Philosophie, I, Thales bis Kyniker, Pierre Garniron & Walter Jaeschke, Herausgegeben, Band 7, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1989).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (8): Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, Teil 3, Griechische Philosophie, II, Plato bis Proklos, Pierre Garniron & Walter Jaeschke, Herausgegeben, Band 8, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1996).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (9): Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie, Teil 4, Philosophie des Mittelalters und der neueren Zeit, Pierre Garniron & Walter Jaeschke, Herausgegeben, Band 9, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1986).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (10): Vorlesungen über die Logik, Berlin 1831,―Nachgeschrieben von Karl Hegel, Udo Rameil, Hrsg., Herausgegeben unter Mitarbeit von Hans–Christian Lucas, Band 10, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2001).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (11): Vorlesungen über Logik und Metaphysik, Heidelberg 1817,―Mitgeschrieben von Franz Anton Good, Karen Gloy, Hrsg., Band 11, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1992).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (12): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Weltgeschichte, Berlin 1822–1823,―Nachschriften von Karl Gustav Julius von Griesheim, Heinrich Gustav Hotho & Friedrich Carl Hermann Victor von Kehler, Karl Brehmer, Karl–Heinz Ilting & Hoo Nam Seelmann, Herausgegeben, Band 12, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1996).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (13): Vorlesung über die Philosophie des Geistes, Berlin 1827–1828,―Nachgeschrieben von Johann Eduard Erdmann & Ferdinand Walter, Franz Hespe & Burkhard Tuschling, Herausgegeben, Band 13, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 1994).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (14): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie des Rechts, Berlin 1819–1820,―Nachgeschrieben von Johann Rudolf Ringier, Emil Angehrn, Martin Bondeli & Hoo Nam Seelmann, Herausgegeben, Band 14, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2000).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (15): Vorlesungen über philosophische Enzyklopädie,
Nürnberg 1812–1813,―Nachschriften von Christian Samuel Meinel & Julius Friedrich Heinrich Abegg, Udo Rameil, Hrsg., Band 15, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2002).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (16): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Natur, Berlin 1819–1820,―Nachgeschrieben von Johann Rudolf Ringier, Martin Bondeli & Hoo Nam Seelmann, Herausgegeben, Band 16, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2002).
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, Vorlesungen, Ausgewählte Nachschriften und Manuskripte (17): Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Natur, Berlin 1825–1826,―Nachgeschrieben von Heinrich Wilhelm Dove, Karol Bal, Gilles Marmasse, Thomas Posch & Klaus Vieweg, Herausgegeben, Band 17, (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2007).
HEGEL’S RECHTSPHILOSOPHIE: SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY 1821–2013
1. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts. Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse. Zum Gebrauch für seine Vorlesungen, [=Originalausgabe] (Berlin: Nicolaische Buchhandlung, 1821).
2. Eduard Gans, Herausgegeber, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, Hrsg., von Eduard Gans, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Werke, Vollstandige Ausgabe durch einem Verein von Freunden des Verewigten, Band 8], (Berlin: Verlag von Duncker und Humblot, 1833). [Zweite Auflage, Berlin 1840; Dritte Auflage, Berlin 1854]
3. Gerardus Johannes Petrus Josephus Bolland, Herausgegeber, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts mit einer Einleitung, (Leiden: A.H. Adriani, 1902).
4. Georg Lasson, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Mit den von Eduard Gans redigierten Zusätzen aus Hegels Vorlesungen, Neu hrsg., von Georg Lasson, [=Hegels sämtliche Werke, Band VI], (Leipzig: Verlag von Felix Meiner, 1911). [Zweite Auflage, Leipzig 1921; Dritte Auflage, Leipzig 1930]
5. Alfred Baeumler, Herausgegeber, Hegels Schriften zur Gesellschaftsphilosophie: Teil I, Philosophie des Geists und Rechtsphilosophie, [=Die Herdflamme, Sammlung der gesellschaftswissenschaftlichen Grundwerke aller Zeiten und Volker, Band 11], (Jena: Verlag von Gustav Fischer, 1927).
6. Hermann Glockner, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschat im Grundrisse, Mit einem Vorwort von Eduard Gans, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Jubiläumsausgabe in zwanzig Bänden, Auf Grund des von Ludwig Boumann, Friedrich Förster, Eduard Gans, Karl Hegel, Leopold von Henning, Heinrich Gustav Hotho, Philipp Marheineke, Karl Ludwig Michelet, Karl Rosenkranz und Johannes Karl Hartwig Schultze besorgten Originaldruckes im Faksimileverfahren, Siebenter Band], (Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt: Fromann, 1928).
7. Johannes Hoffmeister, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, mit Hegels eigenhändigen Randbemerkungen in seinem handexemplar der Rechtsphilosophie, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Sämtliche Werke, Neu kritische Ausgabe, Band XII], (Hamburg: Verlag Felix Meiner, 1955).
8. Karl Löwith & Manfred Riedel, Herausgegeben, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: Studienausgabe in 3 Bänden, Ausgewählt und eingeleitet von Karl Löwith und Manfred Riedel, Band 2] (Frankfurt und Hamburg: Fischer Verlag, 1968).
9. Berhard Lakebrink, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, mit einer Einleitung hrsg., von Berhard Lakebrink, (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1970).
10. Eva Moldenhauer & Karl Markus Michel, Herausgegeben, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, mit Hegels eigenhändigen Notizen und den mündlichen Zusätzen, [=G.W.F. Hegel, Werke in zwanzig Bänden, Band 7], (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1970).
11. Helmut Reichelt, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, mit Hegels eigenhändigen Notizen in seinem Handexemplar und den Mündlichen Zusätzen, (Frankfurt–Berlin–Wien: Ullstein, 1972).
12. Karl–Heinz Ilting, Herausgegeber, Die “Rechtsphilosophie” von 1820 mit Hegels Vorlesungnotizen 1821–1825, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Vorlesungen uber Rechtsphilosophie, 1818–1831: Edition und Kommentar in sechs Banden von Karl–Heinz Ilting, Zweiter Band], (Stuttgard–Bad Cannstatt: Frommann–Holzboog, 1974).
13. Hermann Klenner, Herausgegeber, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder Naturrecht und Staatswissenschaft im Grundrisse, nach der Ausgabe von Eduard Gans herausgegeben und mit einer Einleitung versehen von Hermann Klenner, (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1981).
14. Klaus Grotsch, Elisabeth Weisser–Lohmann & Hermann Klenner, Herausgegeben, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Verfasser des Anhangs Hermann Klenner, [=Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Gesammelte Werke, Band 14, 1–3], (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2009–2011).
15. Horst D. Brandt, Herausgegeber, Philosophische Bibliothek: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Band 638, [Auf der Grundlage der Edition des Textes in den Gesammelten Werken, Band 14], (Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag, 2013).
UNIVERSAL HEGEL BIBLIOGRAPHY (SELECT): SECONDARY SOURCES
George Plimpton Adams, The Mystical Elements in Hegel’s Early Theological Writings: University of California Publications in Philosophy, vol. 2, №4, (Berkeley, California: The University Press, 1910), 67–102.
Rolf Ahlers, “The Absolute as the Beginning of Hegel’s Logic,” Philosophical Forum, 6(1974–1975): 288–300.
Samuel Alexander, “Hegel’s Conception of Nature,” Mind, 11(1886): 495–523.
Horst Althaus, Hegel: An Intellectual Biography, Michael Tarsh, translator, (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000).
Louis Althusser, The Spectre of Hegel: Early Writings, G.M. Goshgarian, translator, (London/New York: Verso, 2014).
Karl Ameriks, “Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46.1(September, 1985): 1–35.
Karl Ameriks, “The Hegelian Critique of Kantian Morality,” New Essays on Kant, Bernard den Ouden & Marcia Moen, editors, (New York: Peter Lang, 1987), 179–212.
Karl Ameriks, “Hegel and Idealism,” The Monist, 74(1991): 386–402.
Anonymous, “Karl Rosenkranz: The Life of Hegel,” The Biblical Repertory and Princeton Review, 20.4(October, 1848): 561–591.
Anonymous, “Was Hegel a Pantheist?” American Quarterly Church Review, and Ecclesiastical Register, John M. Leavitt, editor, 21.3(October, 1869): 382–417.
Anonymous, “Hegel Today,” The Monist, 48.1(January, 1964): ?
Paul Ashton, Toula Nicolacopoulos & George Vassilacopoulos, editors, The Spirit of the Age: Hegel and the Fate of Thinking, (Melbourne: re.press, 2008).
Shlomo Avineri, “Hegel and Nationalism,” Hegel’s Political Philosophy, Walter Kaufmann, editor, (New York: Atherton Press, 1970), 109–116.
Shlomo Avineri, Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972).
Shlomo Avineri, “Hegel and the Emergence of Zionism,” Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 6(Autumn/Winter, 1982): 12–18.
Shlomo Avineri, “The Problem of War in Hegel’s Thought,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, Jon Stewart, editor, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 131–141.
Carl Friedrich Bachmann, On Hegel’s System and the New Transfiguration of Philosophy, (Leipsic, 1833).
James Black Baillie, The Origin and Significance of Hegel’s Logic: A General Introduction to Hegel’s System, (London: Macmillan, 1901).
James Black Baillie (1872–1940), “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopædia of Religion and Ethics: Fiction — Hyksos, vol. 6, James Hastings, John Alexander Selbie and Louis Herbert Gray, editors, (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1955), 568–587. [1913]
James Black Baillie and William Wallace (1844–1897), “Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1945), 379–381.
James Black Baillie and William Wallace (1844–1897), “Hegelian Philosophy,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1945), 381–385.
Karol Bal, “Hegel’s Philosophy of History―Between Dialectics and Metaphysics,” Dialectics and Humanism, 1(1974): 331–338.
Stuart Barnett, editor, Hegel After Derrida, (London: Routledge, 1998).
Karl Barth, “Hegel,” Protestant Thought: From Rousseau to Ritschel, Being the Translation of Eleven Chapters of “Die protestantische Theologie im 19. Jahrhundert,” H.H. Hartwell, translator, (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1959), 268–305. [1947]
Michael Baur, Henry Silton Harris and John Edward Russon, editors, Hegel and the Tradition: Essays in Honor of H.S. Harris, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997).
Michael Baur, “Sublating Kant and the Old Metaphysics: A Reading of the Transition From Being to Essence in Hegel’s Logic,” Owl of Minerva, 29(1998): 139–164.
Louis White Beck, “The Reformation, the Revolution and the Restoration in Hegel’s Political Philosophy,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 14(1976): 51–61.
Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Friedrich Hogemann, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme, Hans Christian Lucas, Kurt Rainer Meist & Hans Josef Schneider, Staff of the Hegel Archives editors, “Description of the Manuscript: The Editors,” Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: The First Philosophy of Right, Heidelberg 1817–1818, With Additions From the Lectures of 1818–1819, G.W.F. Hegel & Peter Wannenmann; J. Michael Stewart & Peter C. Hodgson, editors and translators & Otto Pöggeler, editorial introduction, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 45–47. [1983 & 1995]
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, “Introduction: Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 1–24.
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, “Hegel’s Historicism,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 270–300.
Frederick C. Beiser, “Hegel, A Non–Metaphysician? A Polemic Review of H.T. Engelhardt and Terry Pinkard (eds.), Hegel Rediscovered,” The Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 32(1995): 1–13
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, 2nd edition, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, “Introduction: Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, 2nd edition, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 1–24.
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, “Hegel’s Historicism,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, 2nd edition, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), ?
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, Hegel, (London/New York: Routledge, 2005).
Frederick C. Beiser, editor, The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth–Century Philosophy, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Richard Bellamy, “Hegel and Liberalism,” History of European Ideas, 8(1987): 693–708.
Ermanno Bencivenga, Hegel’s Dialectical Logic, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
Seyla Benhabib, translator, “Translator’s Introduction,” Hegel’s Ontology and the Theory of Historicity, Herbert Marcuse, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1987), ix–xl. [1932+1968]
Robert Bernasconi, “Hegel at the Court of the Ashanti,” Hegel After Derrida, Stuart Barnett, editor, (London: Routledge, 1998), 41–63.
Robert Bernasconi, “Krimskrams: Hegel and the Current Controversy About the Beginnings of Philosophy,” Interrogating the Tradition: Hermeneutics and the Tradition of Philosophy, C.E. Scott & J. Sallis, editors, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2000), 191–208.
Robert Bernasconi, “Religious Philosophy: Hegel’s Occasional Perplexity in the Face of the Distinction Between Philosophy and Religion,” The Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 45/46(2002): 1–15.
Robert Bernasconi, “With What Must the History of Philosophy Begin? Hegel’s Role in the Debate on the Place of India Within the History of Philosophy,” Hegel’s History of Philosophy: New Interpretations, David A. Duquette, editor, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2003), 35–50.
Robert Bernasconi, “With What Must the History of Philosophy Begin? On the Racial Basis of Hegel’s Eurocentricism,” Nineteenth–Century Contexts, 22(2000): 171–201.
Christopher J. Berry, Hume, Hegel and Human Nature, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982).
Daniel Berthold–Bond, Hegel’s Theory of Madness, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1995).
Daniel Berthold–Bond, Hegel’s Grand Synthesis: A Study of Being, Thought, and History, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1989).
Bernard Bosanquet, “Hegel’s Theory of the Political Organism,” Mind: A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy, New Series, George Frederick Stout, editor, 7.25.1(January, 1898): 1–14.
Brady Bowman and Allen Speight, editors and translators, “Introduction,” Heidelberg Writings: Journal Publications, G.W.F. Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), vii–xxiv.
Brady Bowman and Allen Speight, editors and translators, “Translators’ Note,” Heidelberg Writings: Journal Publications, G.W.F. Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), xxv–xxix.
Brady Bowman, Hegel and the Metaphysics of Absolute Negativity, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013).
William J. Brazill, The Young Hegelians, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970).
Harry Brod, Hegel’s Philosophy of Politics, (Boulder, Colorado: Waterview. 1992).
Thom Brooks, Hegel’s Political Philosophy: A Systematic Reading of the Philosophy of Right, 2nd edition, (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2013). [2007]
Robert F. Brown and Peter C. Hodgson, editors and translators, “Editorial Introduction: The Lectures on the Philosophy of World History,” Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Manuscript of the Introduction and the Lectures of 1822–1823, G.W.F. Hegel, Karl Hegel, Karl Gustav Julius von Griesheim, Heinrich Gustav Hotho and Friedrich Carl Hermann Victor von Kehler; William G. Geuss (assistant); Karl Brehmer, Karl–Heinz Ilting, Walter Jaeschke & Hoo Nam Seelmann, German editors, vol. 1, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2011), 1–63.
Gary K. Browning, editor, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Reappraisal, (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997).
Gary K. Browning, Hegel and the History of Political Philosophy, (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1999).
Hendrik Gerrit ten Bruggencate (1880–1954), “Hegel’s Views on War,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 1.1(October, 1950): 58–60.
Randolph Robert John Buchanan, The Concept of Contradiction in Hegel’s Dialectics, Ph.D. thesis, Graeme Nicholson, advisor, (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1995).
Andrew Buchwalter, Dialectics, Politics, and the Contemporary Value of Hegel’s Practical Philosophy, (London: Routledge, 2012).
John W. Burbidge, On Hegel’s Logic: Fragments of a Commentary, (Humanities Press, 1981).
John W. Burbidge et alia, “Preface to the Translation,” The Jena System, 1804–1805: Logic and Metaphysics, G.W.F. Hegel; Lorraine Code, William Carruthers, André Dekker, Martin Donogho, Henry Silton Harris (introduction), Helga Hunter, George Di Giovanni, Kem Luther, Lee Manchester, Jeff Mitscherling, David Pfohl, Peter Preuss, Kenneth Schmitz and Donald Stewart, editors and translators; Hans Ehrenberg, Rolf–Peter Horstmann, Georg Lasson, Herbert Link and Johann Heinrich Trede, German editors, (Kingston/Montréal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 1986), xii–xxiii. [1915–1923–1971]
John W. Burbidge, Hegel On Logic and Religion: The Reasonableness of Christianity, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1992).
John W. Burbidge, “Hegel in Canada,” Owl of Minerva, 25.2(Spring, 1994): 215–219.
John W. Burbidge, Real Process: How Logic and Chemistry Combine in Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, (Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press, 1996).
John W. Burbidge, The Logic of Hegel’s Logic: An Introduction, (Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview Press, 2006).
John W. Burbidge, Hegel’s Systematic Contingency, (New York, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007).
John W. Burbidge, Historical Dictionary of Hegelian Philosophy, 2nd edition, Jon Woronoff, series editor, (Lanham, Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, 2008).
John W. Burbidge, “Introduction,” Historical Dictionary of Hegelian Philosophy, 2nd edition, Jon Woronoff, series editor, (Lanham, Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, 2008),1–20
Richard Burdon (Viscount Haldane), “Introductory Preface,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, vol. 1, By Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Walter Henry Johnston and Leslie Graham Struthers, translators, (London: Cambridge University Press, 1929), 7–15.
Richard Burdon (Viscount Haldane), “Hegel,” The Contemporary Review, 67(February, 1895): 232–245.
Tony Burns, Natural Law and Political Ideology in the Philosophy of Hegel, (Aldershot: Avebury, 1996).
Jonathan Bush, “Hegelian Slaves and the Antebellum South,” Cardozo Law Review, 10.5–6/2 (March–April, 1989): 1517–1563.
Clark Butler, Introduction to the Study of the Logic of Hegel, (?).
Clark Butler, G.W.F. Hegel (Twayne’s World Authors series), vol. 461, (Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1977).
Clark Butler, “Hermeneutic Hegelianism,” Idealistic Studies, 14.2(1985): 121–135.
Clark Butler, Hegel’s Logic: Between Dialectic and History, (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1996).
Clark Butler, “Translator’s Introduction,” Lectures on Logic: Berlin 1831, G.W.F. Hegel and Karl Hegel, transcription; Clark Butler, translator; John Sallis, series editor, (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 2008), vii–xxiii. [2001]
Clark Butler, The Dialectical Method: A Treatise Hegel Never Wrote, (Humanity Books, 2012).
Edward Caird, Hegel, (Edinburgh/London: William Blackwood & Sons, 1883).
Mary Whiton Calkins, “The Order of the Hegelian Argument,” Mind, (1903): ?
David G. Carlson, Drucilla Cornell & Michel Rosenfeld, editors, Hegel and Legal Theory, (New York: Routledge, 1991).
Edgar Frederick Carritt (1876–1964), “Hegel and Prussianism,” Philosophy, 15(1940): 315–317.
Walter Cerf and Henry Silton Harris, editors and translators, “Translators’ Preface,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), vii–ix.
Walter Cerf, editor and translator, “Speculative Philosophy and Intellectual Intuition: An Introduction to Hegel’s Essays,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel; Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), xi–xxxvi.
Walter Cerf and Henry Silton Harris, editors and translators, “Note on the Text and on Conventions,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), xxxvii–xxxviii.
Malcolm Clark, Logic and System: A Study of the Transition From “Vorstellung” to Thought in the Philosophy of Hegel, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1971).
Charles Woolsey Cole, “The Heavy Hand of Hegel,” Nationalism and Internationalism: Essays Inscribed to Carlton J.H. Hayes, Edward Mead Earle, editor, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1950), 65–78.
Lucio Colletti, Marxism and Hegel, L. Garner, translator, (London: Verso Books, 1979).
Robin George Collingwood, “Hegel: The Transition to the Modern View of Nature,” The Idea of Nature, Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor, (London: Oxford University Press, 1970), 121–132. [1945]
Ardis B. Collins, editor, Hegel on the Modern World, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1995).
William E. Conklin, Hegel’s Laws, (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 2008).
Daniel Cook, Language in the Philosophy of Hegel, (The Hague: Mouton, 1973).
Barry Cooper, The End of History: An Essay on Modern Hegelianism, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1984).
D. Cornell, M. Rosenfeld and D.G. Carlson, editors, Hegel and Legal Theory, (London: Routledge,1991).
Youri Courmier, War As Paradox: Clausewitz and Hegel on Fighting Doctrines and Ethics, (Montreal/Kingston: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 2016).
Renato Cristi, Hegel on Freedom and Authority, (Cardiff, Wales: University of Wales Press, 2005).
Stephen Crites, Dialectic and Gospel in the Development of Hegel’s Thinking, (Pennsylvania, PA: Penn State University Press, 1998).
Benedetto Croce (1866–1952), What Is Living and What Is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel, 3rd edition, Douglas Ainslie, translator, (London: Macmillan, 1915). [1906+1912+1915]
Bernard Cullen, Hegel’s Social and Political Thought, (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1979).
Gustavus Watts Cunningham, Thought and Reality in Hegel’s System, (New York: Longmans, Green, 1910).
Fred Reinhard Dallmayr, G.W.F. Hegel: Modernity and Politics, new edition, (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2002). [1993]
Katerina Deligiorgi, editor, Hegel: New Directions, (Montreal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 2006).
Alfred Denker and Michael Vater, editors, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: New Critical Essays, (Amherst, New York: Humanity, 2003).
Martin J. De Nys, “Identity and Difference, Thought and Being,” Identity and Difference: Studies in Hegel’s Logic, Philosophy of Spirit, and Politics, Philip T. Grier, editor, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2007), 83–99.
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Hegel and Modernity, (San Francisco, California: Medium Corporation, 2018).
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Stronghold of Hegel: Modern Enemies of Plato and Hegel, (San Francisco, California: Medium Corporation, 2016).
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Americanism: The New Hegelian Orthodoxy, third edition, (San Francisco, California: Internet Archive, 2016).
Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Americanism: Stronghold of Hegel, Holograph Manuscript, Montreal/Vancouver, 2013.
Willem A. deVries, Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity: An Introduction to Theoretical Spirit, (lthaca, New York/London: Cornell University Press, 1988).
Jacques d’Hondt (1920–2012), Hegel in His Time: Berlin 1818–1831, John W. Burbidge, translator, (Lewiston, New York: Broadview Press, 1988).
Laurence Dickey, Hegel: Religion, Economics, and the Politics of Spirit, 1770–1807, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
Laurence Dickey, editor, “General Introduction,” Political Writings, G.W.F. Hegel; Hugh Barr Nisbet, translator; Raymond Geuss and Quentin Skinner, series editors, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), vii–xli. [1999]
Paul Diesing, Hegel’s Dialectical Political Economy: A Contemporary Application, (Boulder, Colorado: Westview, 1999).
George Di Giovanni, Contingency: Its Foundation in Hegel’s Logic of Becoming, Ph.D thesis, (Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press, 1970).
George Di Giovanni, “The Category of Contingency in the Hegelian Logic,” Art and Logic in Hegel’s Philosophy, Warren E. Steinkraus, editor, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1980), 179–200.
George Di Giovanni and Henry Silton Harris (1926–2007), editors and translators, Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post–Kantian Idealism, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1985). [2nd edition, Indianapolis, 2001]
George Di Giovanni, editor, Essays on Hegel’s Logic, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1990).
George Di Giovanni, “Hegel, Nature, and the Rationalization of Experience,” Dialogue, 32(1993): 783–794.
George Di Giovanni & Harris, translators, “Ænesidemus (excerpt),” Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post–Kantian Idealism, G.E. Schulze, (anonymous), 2nd edition, (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2000), ?
George Di Giovanni, editor and translator, “Introduction,” The Science of Logic, G.W.F. Hegel, Michael Baur, General editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), xi–lxii.
George Di Giovanni, editor and translator, “Translator’s Note,” The Science of Logic, G.W.F. Hegel, Michael Baur, General editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), lxiii–lxxiv.
George Di Giovanni, “Hegelian Logic and Hegelian Myth,” Hegel–Jahrbuch, 2017.1(May, 2017):109–117.
James Alexander Doull (1918–2001), “Hegel and Contemporary Liberalism, Anarchism, Socialism: A Defense of the Rechtsphilosophie Against Marx and His Contemporary Followers,” The Legacy of Hegel, Joseph J. O’Malley, Keith Warren Algozin and Frederick Gustav Weiss, editors, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973), ?
Horatio Willis Dresser (1866–1954), “The Element of Irrationality in the Hegelian Dialectic: Supplementary Essay,” The Philosophy of the Spirit: A Study of the Spiritual Nature of Man and the Presence of God, with a Supplementary Essay on the Logic of Hegel, (New York/London: G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1908), 385–537.
Will Dudley, Hegel and History, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2010).
Raya Dunayevskaya, “Hegel’s Absolute As New Beginning,” Art and Logic in Hegel’s Philosophy, Warren E. Steinkraus & Kenneth L. Schmitz, editors, (Humanities Press, 1980), ?
David A. Duquette, editor, Hegel’s History of Philosophy: New Interpretations, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2003).
David A. Duquette, editor, “Introduction,” Hegel’s History of Philosophy: New Interpretations, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2003), 1–15.
David A. Duquette, Hegel: Philosophy of History (Oxford Bibliographies Online Research Guide), (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Samuel W. Dyde, translator, “Translator’s Preface,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, (London: George Bell & Sons, 1896), ix–xiii.
Hugo Tristram Engelhardt Jr. and Terry P. Pinkard, editors, Hegel Rediscovered: Beyond Metaphysics and the Authoritarian State, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994).
Johann Eduard Erdmann, Outlines of Logic and Metaphysics, B.C. Burt, translator, (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1896).
Johann Eduard Erdmann, “Hegel’s Panlogism,” A History of Philosophy: Modern Philosophy, 4th German edition, vol. 2, Williston S. Hough, translator, (London: Swann Sonnenschein, 1897), 682–705.
Charles Carroll Everett, The Science of Thought: A System of Logic, (London, ?).
Emil Ludwig Fackenheim, The Religious Dimension of Hegel’s Thought, (1968).
Alfredo Ferrarin, Hegel and Aristotle, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Réal R. Fillion, “Realizing Reason in History: How Cunning Does It Have To Be?” Owl of Minerva, 23.1(Fall, 1991): 77–92.
John Niemeyer Findlay, “Foreward,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, G.W.F. Hegel; Arnold Vincent Miller (1899–1991), translator, (New York: The Humanities Press, 1976), 11. [1969]
John Niemeyer Findlay, “Forward,” Phenomenology of Spirit, G.W.F. Hegel, Arnold Vincent Miller, translator, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), v–xxx. [1977]
John Niemeyer Findlay, The Philosophy of Hegel: An Introduction and Re–examination, (New York: Collier Books, 1962). [1958]
Joseph C. Flay, “Bibliography,” Hegel and the History of Philosophy, Joseph J. O’Malley, Keith W. Algozin, and Frederick G. Weiss, editors, (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1974), 194–236.
Joseph C. Flay, Hegel’s Quest for Certainty, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1984).
Eugene (Yakov) Fleishmann, “Hegels Umgestaltung der kantischen Logik,” Hegel–Studien, 2(1965): 181–207.
Robert Flint (1838–1910), “Hegel,” The Philosophy of History in Europe: The Philosophy of History in France and Germany, vol. 1, (Edinburgh/London: William Blackwood & Sons, 1874), 496–541.
Robert Flint, Historical Philosophy in France and French Belgium and Switzerland, (Edinburgh/London: William Blackwood & Sons, 1893).
Duncan Forbes, editor, “Introduction,” Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction: Reason in World History, G.W.F. Hegel and Karl Hegel; Hans Reiss, assistant & Hugh Barr Nisbet, editor and translator; Johannes Hoffmeister, German editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), vii–xxxv. [1840–1955–1975]
Michael N. Forster, Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998).
Michael Beresford Foster (1903–1959), “The Opposition Between Hegel and the Philosophy of Empiricism,” Verhandlungen des dritten Hegelkongresses vom 19 bis 23, April 1933 in Rom, Baltus Wigersma (1877–1962), editor, (Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1934), 79–96.
Michael Beresford Foster, The Political Philosophies of Plato and Hegel, (New York: Russell and Russell, 1965). [1935]
Paul Franco, Hegel’s Philosophy of Freedom, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999).
Carl Joachim Friedrich, editor and translator, The Philosophy of Hegel, (New York: Modern Library, 1953–1954).
Carl Joachim Friedrich, editor and translator, “Introduction,” The Philosophy of Hegel, (New York: Modern Library, 1953–1954), xiii–lxiv.
Carl Joachim Friedrich, “The Power of Negation: Hegel’s Dialectic and Totalitarian Ideology,” A Hegel Symposium, Don Carlos Travis, editor, (Austin, Texas: University of Texas, 1962), 13–35.
Benjamin Apthorp Gould Fuller (1879–1956), “Hegel,” A History of Philosophy, (New York: Henry Holt, 1938), 401–454.
Peter Fuss, “Avineri’s Hegel,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 13.2(April, 1975): 235–246.
Hans–Georg Gadamer, Hegel’s Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, P. Christopher Smith, translation and introduction, (New Haven/London: Yale University Press, 1976). [1971]
Hans–Georg Gadamer, “Hegel’s Inverted World,” Hegel’s Dialectic: Five Hermeneutical Studies, P. Christopher Smith, translation and introduction, (New Haven/London: Yale University Press, 1976), 35–53. [1971]
Shaun Gallagher, editor, Hegel, History, and Interpretation, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1997).
Abel Garza Jr., “Hegel’s Critique of Liberalism and Natural Law: Reconstructing Ethical Life,” Law and Philosophy, (1991): 371–398.
Ido Geiger, The Founding Act of Modern Ethical Life: Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral and Political Philosophy, (Stanford, California: Stanford University Press, 2007).
Theodore D. George, Tragedies of Spirit: Tracing Finitude in Hegel’s Phenomenology, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2006).
Theodore F. Geraets, Henry Silton Harris and Wallis Arthur Suchting, editors and translators, “Translators’ Preface,” The Encyclopaedia Logic with the Zusätze: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With the Zusätze, G.W.F. Hegel, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991), vii–ix.
Theodore F. Geraets, “The End of the History of Religions ‘Grasped in Thought,’” Hegel–Studien, 24(1989): 55–77.
Theodore F. Geraets, editor, Hegel: The Absolute Spirit, (Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press, 1984).
Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, “Introduction: The Shape and Influence of Hegel’s Aesthetics,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Art: The Hotho Transcript of the 1823 Berlin Lectures, Robert F. Brown, editor and translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2014), 7–176.
Michael Allan Gillespie, Hegel, Heidegger, and the Ground of History, (Chicago: University of chicago Press, 1984).
William H. Goetzmann, editor, The American Hegelians: An Intellectual Episode in the History of Western America, (New York: Knopf, 1973).
Joshua D. Goldstein, Hegel’s idea of the Good Life: From Virtue to Freedom: Early Writings and Mature Political Philosophy, (Dordrecht: Springer, 2006).
James A. Good, A Search For Unity in Diversity: The “Permanent Hegelian Deposit” in the Philosophy of John Dewey, (New York: Lexington Books, 2006).
Moltke Gramm, “Moral and Literary Ideals in Hegel’s Critique of ‘the Moral World–View,’” Clio, 7.3(1978): 375–402.
Philip T. Grier, “The End of History and the Return of History,” Owl of Minerva, 21.2(Spring, 1990): 131–144.
Philip T. Grier, editor, Identity and Difference: Studies in Hegel’s Logic, Philosophy of Spirit, and Politics, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2007).
Jesse Glenn Gray (1913–1977), Hegel’s Hellenic Ideal, (New York: King’s Crown Press, 1941).
Jesse Glenn Gray, “Hegel’s Logic: The Philosophy of the Concrete,” Virginia Quarterly, 47.2(1971): 175–189.
Murray Greene, Hegel on the Soul, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1970).
Franz Grégoire, “A Semi–Legend: The Divinity of the State in Hegel,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, Jon Stewart, editor, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 289–300.
Philip Grier, editor, Identity and Difference: Studies in Hegel’s Logic and Politics, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2007).
Paul Guyer, “Thought and Being: Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Theoretical Philosophy,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, 1st edition, Frederick C. Beiser, editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993): 171–210.
Viscount Haldane (Richard Burdon), “Introductory Preface,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, vol. 1, Hegel; Walter Henry Johnston and Leslie Graham Struthers, translators, (London: Cambridge University Press, 1929), 7–15.
Hiralal Haldar, Neo–Hegelianism, (London: Heath Cranton, Ltd., 1927).
Hiralal Haldar, Essays in Philosophy, (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1920).
Hiralal Haldar, “Some Aspects of Hegel’s Philosophy,” Philosophical Review, 5(1 May 1896): 263–277.
Michael O. Hardimon, Hegel’s Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994).
Errol Eustace Harris (1908–2009), “The Philosophy of Nature in Hegel’s System,” The Review of Metaphysics, 3.2.10(December, 1949): 213–228.
Errol Eustace Harris, “Dialectic and Scientific Method,” Idealistic Studies, 3.1(January, 1973): 1–17.
Errol Eustace Harris, An Interpretation of the Logic of Hegel, (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1983).
Errol Eustace Harris, The Spirit of Hegel, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1993).
Errol Eustace Harris, “Hegel’s Theory of Sovereignty, International Relations, and War,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, Jon Stewart, editor, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 154–166.
Henry Silton Harris (1926–2007), Hegel’s Development: Toward the Sunlight, 1770–1801, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972).
Henry Silton Harris and Walter Cerf, editors and translators, “Translators’ Preface,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), vii–ix.
Henry Silton Harris and Walter Cerf, editors and translators, “Note on the Text and on Conventions,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), xxxvii–xxxviii.
Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, “Introduction to the Difference Essay,” The Difference Between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, G.W.F. Hegel; Walter Cerf, editor and translator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1977), 1–75.
Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, “Hegel’s System of Ethical Life: An Interpretation,” System of Ethical Life (1802–1803) and the First Philosophy of Spirit (Part 3 of the System of Speculative Philosophy 1803–1804), G.W.F. Hegel; Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor and translator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1979), 1–96.
Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, “Introduction: Hegel’s First Philosophy of Spirit,” System of Ethical Life (1802–1803) and the First Philosophy of Spirit (Part 3 of the System of Speculative Philosophy 1803–1804), G.W.F. Hegel; Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor and translator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1979), 189–204.
Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, “A Note on the Translation,” System of Ethical Life (1802–1803) and the First Philosophy of Spirit (Part 3 of the System of Speculative Philosophy 1803–1804), G.W.F. Hegel; Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor and translator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1979), 266–269.
Henry Silton Harris and Thomas Malcolm Knox, editors and translators, “Hegel’s System of Ethical Life: A Note on the Translation,” System of Ethical Life (1802–1803) and the First Philosophy of Spirit (Part 3 of the System of Speculative Philosophy 1803–1804), G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1979), 99.
Henry Silton Harris, editor, “The Hegel Renaissance in the Anglo–Saxon World Since 1945,” The Owl of Minerva, 15.1(Fall, 1983): 77–106.
Henry Silton Harris, editor, The Philosophy of Hegel, (New York: Garland Publishing, 1984).
Henry Silton Harris & George Di Giovanni, editors and translators, Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post–Kantian Idealism, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1985). [2nd edition, Indianapolis, 2001]
Henry Silton Harris, “Preface to the Commentary,” The Jena System, 1804–1805: Logic and Metaphysics, G.W.F. Hegel; John W. Burbidge, Lorraine Code, William Carruthers, André Dekker, Martin Donogho, Helga Hunter, George Di Giovanni, Kem Luther, Lee Manchester, Jeff Mitscherling, David Pfohl, Peter Preuss, Kenneth Schmitz and Donald Stewart, editors and translators; Hans Ehrenberg, Rolf–Peter Horstmann, Georg Lasson, Herbert Link and Johann Heinrich Trede, German editors, (Kingston/Montréal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 1986), xii–xxiii. [1915–1923–1971]
Henry Silton Harris, “General Introduction,” The Jena System, 1804–1805: Logic and Metaphysics, G.W.F. Hegel; John W. Burbidge, Lorraine Code, William Carruthers, André Dekker, Martin Donogho, Helga Hunter, George Di Giovanni, Kem Luther, Lee Manchester, Jeff Mitscherling, David Pfohl, Peter Preuss, Kenneth Schmitz and Donald Stewart, editors and translators; Hans Ehrenberg, Rolf–Peter Horstmann, Georg Lasson, Herbert Link and Johann Heinrich Trede, German editors, (Kingston/Montréal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 1986), xii–xxiii. [1915–1923–1971]
Henry Silton Harris, Theodore F. Geraets and Wallis Arthur Suchting, editors and translators, “Translators’ Preface,” The Encyclopaedia Logic with the Zusätze: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With the Zusätze, G.W.F. Hegel, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991), vii–ix.
Henry Silton Harris, editor and translator, “Introduction: Translating Hegel’s Logic,” The Encyclopaedia Logic with the Zusatze: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With the Zusatze, G.W.F. Hegel; Theodore F. Geraets and Wallis Arthur Suchting, editors and translators, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991), xiii–xxxi.
Henry Silton Harris, Hegel: Phenomenology and System, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett, 1995).
Henry Silton Harris, Hegel’s Ladder: The Pilgrimage of Reason, vol. 1, (Indianapolis: Hackett Publications, 1997).
Henry Silton Harris, Hegel’s Ladder: The Odyssey of Spirit, vol. 2, (Indianapolis: Hackett Publications, 1997).
Henry Silton Harris, Michael Baur and John Edward Russon, editors, Hegel and the Tradition: Essays in Honor of H.S. Harris, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997).
William Torrey Harris, Hegel’s Logic: A Book on the Genesis of the Categories of the Mind, (Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Company, 1890).
William Torrey Harris, “Introduction to Hegel’s Philosophic Method,” Hegel As the National Philosopher of Germany, Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz; Granville Stanley Hall, translator, (Saint Louis, Missouri: Gray, Baker & Company, 1874), 1–16.
Stuart Jay Harten, Raising the Veil of History: Orientalism, Classicism and the Birth of Western Civilization in Hegel’s Berlin Lecture Courses of the 1820’s, (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1994).
Klaus Hartmann, “Hegel: A Non–Metaphysical View,” Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, Alasdair MacIntyre, editor, (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1972), 101–124.
Joseph Haven (1816–1874), “Hegel,” A History of Philosophy: Ancient and Modern, (New York: Butler, Sheldon & Company, 1876), 382–389.
Martin Heidegger, Hegel’s Concept of Experience, Kenley Royce Dove, translator, (New York: Harper & Row, 1970). [1950]
Martin Heidegger, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, Parvis Emad and Kenneth May, translators, (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1988).
Robert Heiss, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Marx: Three Great Philosophers Whose Ideas Changed the Course of Civilization, (New York: Delta Books, 1975). [1963]
Dieter Henrich, The Course of Remembrance and Other Essays on Holderlin, (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997).
Dieter Henrich, Between Kant and Hegel: Lectures on German Idealism, David S. Pacini, editor, (Cambridge: Canbridge University Press, 2003).
John Grier Hibben, Hegel’s Logic: An Essay in Interpretation, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1902).
Louis P. Hinchman, Hegel’s Critique of the Enlightenment, (Gainesville: University Presses of Florida, 1984).
Peter C. Hodgson, Hegel and Christian Theology: A Reading of the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005).
Peter C. Hodgson, editor and translator, “Translators’ Preface,” Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: The First Philosophy of Right, Heidelberg 1817–1818, With Additions From the Lectures of 1818–1819, G.W.F. Hegel & Peter Wannenmann; J. Michael Stewart & Peter C. Hodgson, translators; Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Friedrich Hogemann, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme, Hans Christian Lucas, Kurt Rainer Meist & Hans Josef Schneider, Staff of the Hegel Archives editors, Otto Pöggeler, Editorial Introduction, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), vii–viii. [1983 & 1995]
Richard Hoenigswald, “Philosophy of Hegelianism,” Twentieth Century Philosophy: Living Schools of Thought, Dagobert David Runes, editor, (New York: Philosophical Library, 1947), 265–291.
Reinhold Friedrich Alfred Hoernlé (1880–1943), “The Idealism of Kant and Hegel,” Idealism As a Philosophical Doctrine, (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1924), 173–159.
Shannon Hoff, The Laws of the Spirit: A Hegelian Theory of Justice, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2014).
Michael H. Hoffheimer, “Does Hegel Justify Slavery?” Owl of Minerva, 25(1993): 118–119.
Michael H. Hoffheimer, Eduard Gans and the Hegelian Philosophy of Law, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishing, 1995).
Michael H. Hoffheimer, “Hegel, Race, Genocide,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 39(2001): 35–61.
Michael H. Hoffheimer, “Race and Law in Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion,” Race and Racism in Modern Philosophy, Andrew Valls, editor, (Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press, 2005), 194–216.
Ted Honderich, editor, “Hegel,” A Companion to Philosophy, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ?), 339–343.
Axel Honneth, The Pathologies of Individual Freedom: Hegel’s Social Theory, Ladislaus Lob, translator, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2010).
Sidney Hook, “Hegel and His Apologists,” Hegel’s Political Philosophy, Walter Kaufmann, editor, (New York: Atherton Press, 1970), 87–105.
Sidney Hook, “Hegel Rehabilitated,” Hegel’s Political Philosophy, Walter Kaufmann, editor, (New York: Atherton Press, 1970), 55–70.
Rolf–Peter Horstmann, “Substance, Subject and Infinity: A Case Study of the Role of Logic in Hegel’s System,” Hegel: New Directions, Katerina Deligiorgi, editor, (Montreal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 2006), 69–84.
Stephen Houlgate, “World History as the Progress of Consciousness: An Interpretation of Hegel’s Philosophy of History,” Owl of Minerva, 22.1(Fall, 1990): 69–80.
Stephen Houlgate, Freedom, Truth and History: An Introduction to Hegel’s Philosophy, (London/New York: Routledge, 1991).
Stephen Houlgate, Hegel and the Philosophy of Nature, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1998).
Stephen Houlgate, “Substance, Causality, and the Question of Method in Hegel’s Science of Logic,” The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, Sally Sedgwick, editor, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 232–252.
Stephen Houlgate, An Introduction to Hegel: Freedom, Truth and History, 2nd edition, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005).
Stephen Houlgate, The Opening of Hegel’s Logic, (West Lafayette, IN: Purdie University Press, 2006).
Stephen Houlgate, editor, “Introduction,” Outlines of the Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel; Thomas Malcolm Knox, translator, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), vii–xxxiii.
Michel Hulin, Hegel et l’Orient, (Paris: J. Vrin, 1974).
Kimberly Hutchings, “Perpetual War/Perpetual Peace: Kant, Hegel and the End of History,” Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 12.1–2.23/24(January, 1991): 39–50.
Jean Hyppolite, Studies in Marx and Hegel, (London: Heinemann, 1969).
Jean Hyppolite, Introduction to Hegel’s Philosophy of History, Bond Harris and Jacqueline Bouchard Spurlock, translator & Arkady Plotnitsky, (Gainesville, Florida: University Press of Florida, 1996).
Jean Hyppolite, Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology, Samuel Cherniak and John Heckman, translators, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1974). [1946]
Jean Hyppolite, Genesis and Structure of Hegel’s Phenomenology, (Chicago: Northwestern University Press, 1997).
Jean Hyppolite, Logic and Existence, Leonard Lawlor and Amit Sen, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1997). [1932]
Heikki Ikäheimo, Self–Consciousness and Intersubjectivity: A Study of Hegel’s Encyclopedia Philosophy of Subjective Spirit (1830), vol. 67, (Jyväskylä, Finland: University of Jyväskylä Publications in Philosophy, 2000).
Evald Vasilyevich Ilyenkov (1924–1979), Dialectical Logic: Essays on its History and Theory, H. Campbell Creighton, translator, (Delhi: Aakar Books, 2008).
Michael Inwood, editor, Hegel, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983).
Michael Inwood, A Hegel Dictionary, (Oxford: Basil Blackwell Publishers, 1997).
Cyril Lionel Robert James (1901–1989 ), Notes on Dialectics: Hegel, Marx, Lenin, (London: Allison & Busby, 1980).
William James, “Absolutism and Empiricism,” Mind, 9(1884): 281–286.
William James, “Hegel and His Method,” Hibbert Journal, 7(1908–1909): 63–75.
Daniel P. Jamros, The Human Shape of God: Religion in Hegel’s Phenomenology, (New York: Paragon, 1994).
Philip J. Kain, Hegel and the Other: A Study of the Phenomenology of Spirit, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2005).
Howard P. Kainz, Hegel’s Phenomenology, Part I: Analysis and Commentary, (Tuscaloosa, Alabama: University of Alabama Press, 1976).
Howard P. Kainz, Hegel’s Phenomenology, Part II: The Evolution of Ethical and Religious Consciousness to the Dialectical Standpoint, (Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1983).
Howard P. Kainz, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: Not Missing the Trees for the Forrest, (Lanham, Maryland: Lexington, 2008).
Howard P. Kainz, G.W.F. Hegel: The Philosophical System, (New York: Twayne Publishers, 1996).
Howard P. Kainz, An Introduction to Hegel: The Stages of Modern Philosophy, (Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1996).
P. Kalisch, Letters Against the Hegelian Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences, 2 vols., (Berlin: Enslin, 1829–1830).
P. Kalisch, Briefe gegen die Hegel’sche Encyclopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaft: Vom Standpunkte der Encyclopädie und der Philosophie, Band 1, (Berlin: Enslin, 1829).
P. Kalisch, Briefe gegen die Hegel’sche Encyclopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaft: Vom Verstande der Encyclopädie und der Philosophie, Band 2, (Berlin: Enslin, 1830).
Walter Kaufmann, “The Hegel Myth and Its Method,” The Philosophical Review, 60.4(October, 1951): ?
Walter Kaufmann, “Hegel’s Early Anti–Theological Phase,” Philosophical Review, 63(1954): 3–18.
Walter Kaufmann, Hegel: Reinterpretation, Texts and Commentary, 2 vols., (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1965).
Walter Kaufmann, Hegel: Reinterpretation, Texts and Commentary, 2 vols., (New York: Anchor Books, 1966). [1965]
Walter Kaufmann, editor, Hegel’s Political Philosophy, (New York: Atherton Press, 1970).
John Steinfort Kedney (1819–1911), Hegel’s Aesthetics: A Critical Exposition, (Chicago, Illinois: S.C. Griggs, 1885).
George Armstrong Kelly, Idealism, Politics and History: Sources of Hegelian Thought, (Cambridge: Canbridge University Press, 1969).
George Armstrong Kelly, Hegel’s Retreat From Eleusis, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978).
Michael Kelly, Hegel’s Charlatanism Exposed, (London: George Allen & Company, 1911).
Hubert Kiesewetter, Von Hegel zu Hitler: Eine Analyse der Hegelschen Machtstaatsideologie und der politischen Wirkungsgeschichte des Rechts–Hegelianismus, (Hamburg: Hoffmann & Campe, 1974).
Dogan Baris Kilinc, Marx’s Critique of Hegel: Stages in Marx’s Approriation of Dialectic, (Ankara: Middle East Technical University, 2013).
Ben Kimpel, Hegel’s Philosophy of History, (Boston: Studen Outlines Co., 1963).
Dudley Knowles, Hegel and the Philosophy of Right (Routledge Philosophy GuideBooks), Tim Crane and Jonathan Wolff, series editors, (London/New York: Routledge, 2002).
Thomas Malcolm Knox, “Hegel and Prussianism,” Philosophy, 15(1940): 51–63. [1935]
Thomas Malcolm Knox, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: William Benton, 1967), 298–303.
Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor and translator, “Translator’s Forward,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978), v–xiii. [1952]
Thomas Malcolm Knox, editor and translator, “Prefatory Note,” On Christianity: Early Theological Writings, G.W.F. Hegel, Richard Kroner, introduction, (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1961), v–viii. [1948]
Thomas Malcolm Knox and Henry Silton Harris, editors and translators, “Hegel’s System of Ethical Life: A Note on the Translation,” System of Ethical Life (1802–1803) and the First Philosophy of Spirit (Part 3 of the System of Speculative Philosophy 1803–1804), G.W.F. Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1979), 99.
David Lamb, editor, Hegel (International Library of Critical Essays in the History of Philosophy), 2 vols, (Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth, 1998).
Quentin Lauer, Hegel’s Idea of Philosophy, (New York: Fordham University Press, 1974).
Quentin Lauer, “The Life of Consciousness and the World Come Alive: Nature, Self–Consciousness in Hegel’s Phenomenology,” Hegel and Whitehead, G.R. Lucas, editor, (New York: SUNY Press, 1986), 186–206.
Thomas Martin Lindsay (1843–1914), “Recent Hegelian Contributions to English Philosophy,” Mind: Old Series, 2(1877): 476–493.
Jacob Loewenberg (1882–1969), “The Life of Georg Wilhelm Freidrich Hegel,” The German Classics of the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries: Masterpieces of German Literature, vol. 7, Kuno Francke, editor, (New York: The German Publication Society, 1913), 1–15.
Jacob Loewenberg, “Editor’s Preface,” Lectures on Modern Idealism, Josiah Royce, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919), vii–xii.
Jacob Loewenberg, Hegel’s Phenomenology: Dialogues on the Life of Mind, (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 1965).
Domenico Losurdo, Hegel and the Freedom of Moderns, (Durham/London: Duke University Press, 2004).
Karl Löwith (1897–1973), From Hegel to Nietzsche: The Revolution in Nineteenth–Century Thought, David E. Green, translator, (Garden City, New York: 1967).
David Easton Loyd, Hegel’s First American Followers the Ohio Hegelians: John B. Stallo, Peter Kaufmann, Moncure Conway, and August Willich, With Key Writings, (Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1966).
George Ramsdell Lucas Jr. and George L. Kline, editors, Hegel and Whitehead, (New York: State University of New York Press, 1986).
Hans Christian Lucas, “The ‘Sovereign Ingratitude’ of Spirit Toward Nature,” The Owl of Minerva, 23.2(Spring, 1992): 131–150.
György Lukács (1885–1971), The Young Hegel, Rodney Livingston, translator, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1975).
Timothy C. Luther, Hegel’s Critique of Modernity: Reconciling Individual Freedom and the Community, (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc., 2009).
David MacGregor, The Communist Ideal in Hegel and Marx, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1984).
Alasdair MacIntyre, editor, Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1972).
John Stuart Mackenzie (1860–1935), “The Hegelian Point of View,” Mind: New Series, 11(1902): 54–71.
Robert Mackintosh (1858–1933), Hegel and Hegelianism, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1903).
Henry Stewart Macran (1867–1937), “Preface,” Hegel’s Doctrine of Formal Logic, Being a Translation of the First Section of the Subjective Logic With Introduction and Notes, Hegel; Henry Stewart Macran, editor and translator, introduction, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), 3–5.
Henry Stewart Macran, “Introduction,” Hegel’s Doctrine of Formal Logic, Being a Translation of the First Section of the Subjective Logic With Introduction and Notes, Hegel; Henry Stewart Macran, editor and translator, introduction, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), 7–110.
Henry Stewart Macran, “Note on the Contrast Between the Hegelian and Popular Conceptions of Formal Logic,” Hegel’s Doctrine of Formal Logic, Being a Translation of the First Section of the Subjective Logic With Introduction and Notes, Hegel; Henry Stewart Macran, editor and translator, introduction, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), 285–295.
Henry Stewart Macran, “Note on Hegel’s Theory of the Syllogistic Figures,” Hegel’s Doctrine of Formal Logic, Being a Translation of the First Section of the Subjective Logic With Introduction and Notes, Hegel; Henry Stewart Macran, editor and translator, introduction, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), 296–303.
Henry Stewart Macran, “Notes,” Hegel’s Doctrine of Formal Logic, Being a Translation of the First Section of the Subjective Logic With Introduction and Notes, Hegel; Henry Stewart Macran, editor and translator, introduction, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1912), 304–315.
Glenn Alexander Magee, The Hegel Dictionary, (2010).
Josef Maier, On Hegel’s Critique of Kant,, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1939).
William Maker, Philosophy Without Foundations: Rethinking Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1994).
Herbert Marcuse, Hegel’s Ontology and the Theory of Historicity, Seyla Benhabib, translator, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1987). [1932+1968]
Troward Harvey Marshall, A Study of the Origins of Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Thesis, 1910).
Karl Marx, Critique of Hegel’s “Philosophy of Right,” Annette Jolin and Joseph O’Malley, translators, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
Werner Marx, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: Its Point and Purpose, (New York: Harper, 1974).
Joseph McCarney, Hegel on History, (London: Routledge, 2000).
John H. McClendon III, C.L.R. James’s Notes on Dialectics: Left Hegelianism or Marxism–Leninism? (New York: Lexington Books, 2005).
John McCumber, The Company of Words: Hegel, Language, and Systematic Philosophy, (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1993).
Sean J. McGrath and Joseph Carew, editors and contributors, “Introduction: What Remains of German Idealism?” Rethinking German Idealism, Joseph Carew, Wes Furlotte, Jean–Christophe Goddard, Adrian Johnston, Cem Kömürcü, Sean J. McGrath, Constantin Rauer, Alexander Schnell, F. Scott Scribner, Devin Zane Shaw, Konrad Utz, Jason M. Wirth, contributors, (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016), 1–19.
Sean J. McGrath and Joseph Carew, editors and contributors, Rethinking German Idealism, Joseph Carew, Wes Furlotte, Jean–Christophe Goddard, Adrian Johnston, Cem Kömürcü, Sean J. McGrath, Constantin Rauer, Alexander Schnell, F. Scott Scribner, Devin Zane Shaw, Konrad Utz, Jason M. Wirth, contributors, (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016).
Evander Bradley McGilvary (1864–1953), “The Dialectical Method I,” Mind: A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy, New Series, George Frederick Stout, editor, 7.25.4(January, 1898): 55–70.
Evander Bradley McGilvary, “The Dialectical Method II,” Mind: A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy, New Series, George Frederick Stout, editor, 7.26.6(April, 1898): 233–242.
Evander Bradley McGilvary, “The Dialectical Method (Conclusion) III,” Mind: A Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy, New Series, George Frederick Stout, editor, 7.27.5(July, 1898): 388–403.
David McLellan, The Young Hegelians and Karl Marx, (London: Macmillan, 1969).
John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart, Studies in the Hegelian Dialectic, 2nd edition, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1922). [1896]
John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart, Studies in Hegelian Cosmology, 2nd edition, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1918). [1901]
John McTaggart Ellis McTaggart, A Commentary on Hegel’s Logic, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1910).
Vrajendra Rag Mehta, Hegel and the Modern State: An Introduction to Hegel’s Political Thought, (New Delhi: Associated Publishing House, 1968).
Friedrich Meinecke (1862–1954), “Hegel: Machiavellism, Idealism and Historicism in Recent German History,” Machiavellism: The Doctrine of Raison d’État and Its Place in Modern History, Douglas Scott, translator, Werner Stark (1909–1985), introduction, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1962), 343–369. [1957]
Yitzhak Y. Melamed and Peter Thielke, “Hegelianism,” New Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Game Theory to Lysenkoism, vol. 3, Maryanne Cline Horowitz, editor in chief, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 2005), 975–977.
Maurice Merleau–Ponty, “Hegel’s Existentialism,” Sense and Non–Sense, Herbert L. Dreyfus & Patricia Allen Dreyfus, translators, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 63–70.
Maurice Merleau–Ponty, Adventures of the Dialectic, Joseph Bien, translator, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1973).
Karl Ludwig Michelet, German editor, “Forward,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, G.W.F. Hegel, vol. 1, Michael John Petry, editor and translator, introduction and explanatory notes, (London: George Allen & Unwin, Ltd., 1970), 179–190. [1842–1965]
Arnold Vincent Miller (1899–1991), translator, “Translator’s Preface,” Hegel’s Science of Logic, G.W.F. Hegel; John Niemeyer Findlay, Foreward, (New York: The Humanities Press, 1976), 13–14. [1969]
Patricia Jagentowicz Mills, editor, Feminist Interpretations of G.W.F. Hegel, (University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996).
Michael H. Mitias, Moral Foundations of the State in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: Anatomy of an Argument, (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1984).
Darrel Moellendorf, “Racism and Rationality in Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit,” History of Political Thought, 13.2(Summer, 1992): 343–355.
Douglas Moggach, The New Hegelians: Politics and Philosophy in the Hegelian School, (New York: cambridge University Press, 2006).
John Daniel Morell (1816–1891), “Hegel,” Historical and Critical View of the Speculative Philosophy of Europe in the Nineteenth Century, 2nd edition, 1 volume edition, (New York: Robert Carter, 1848), 456–477. [1846]
George Sylvester Morris (1840–1889), Hegel’s Philosophy of the State and History: An Exposition, (Chicago: S.C. Griggs & Company, 1887).
Dean Moyar and Michael Quante, editors, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Gustav Emil Mueller (Müller), “Hegel in Amerika,” Zeitschrift für Deutsche Kulturphilosophie, 5(1939): 269.
Gustav Emil Mueller (Müller), “The Hegel Legend of Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 19(1958): 411–?
Gustav Emil Mueller (Müller), “Hegel’s Absolute and the Crisis of Christianity,” A Hegel Symposium, Don Carlos Travis, editor, (Austin, Texas: University of Texas, 1962), 83–112.
Gustav Emil Mueller (Müller), Hegel: The Man, His Vision and Work, (New York: Pageant Press, Inc., 1968).
John Henry Muirhead (1855–1940), “Hegelianism in England,” Encyclopædia Britannica, vol. 13, (New York: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1911), 207.
John Henry Muirhead, The Platonic Tradition in Anglo–Saxon Philosophy, (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1931).
Geoffrey Reginald Gilchrist Mure, An Introduction to Hegel, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1948).
Geoffrey Reginald Gilchrist Mure, “The Organic State,” Philosophy, (1949):
Geoffrey Reginald Gilchrist Mure, A Study of Hegel’s Logic, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). [1950]
Geoffrey Reginald Gilchrist Mure, The Philosophy of Hegel, (London: Oxford University Press, 1965).
James Augustus Henry Murray (1837–1915), Henry Bradley (1845–1923), William Alexander Craigie (1867–1957) & Charles Talbot Onions (1873–1965), editors, “Sublate: Definition III,” A New English Dictionary on Historical Principles Founded Mainly on the Materials Collected by the Philological Society: Su–Th, Part 2, vol. 9, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1919), 28.
Jean–Luc Nancy, Hegel: The Restlessness of the Negative, Jason Smith & Steven Miller, translators, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002).
Dalia Nassar, The Romantic Absolute, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014).
Franz Gabriel Nauen, Revolution, Idealism and Human Freedom: Schelling, Hölderlin and Hegel and the Crisis of Early German Idealism, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1971).
Joseph L. Navickas, Consciousness and Reality: Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjectivity, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1976).
Frederick Neuhouser, Foundations of Hegel’s Social Theory: Actualizing Freedom, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2000).
Hugh Barr Nisbet, translator, “Translator’s Preface,” Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction: Reason in World History, G.W.F. Hegel and Karl Hegel; Hans Reiss, assistant & Duncan Forbes, editor, introduction; Johannes Hoffmeister, German editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), xxxvii–xxxviii. [1840–1955–1975]
Hugh Barr Nisbet, translator, “Translator’s Preface,” Elements of the Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel; Allen W. Wood, editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), xxxv–xliv. [1991]
Hugh Barr Nisbet, translator, “Translator’s Preface,” Political Writings, G.W.F. Hegel; Laurence Dickey, editor; Raymond Geuss and Quentin Skinner, series editors, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), xlv–xlviii. [1999]
Richard Norman, Hegel’s Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction, (London: Sussex University Press, 1976).
Angelica Nuzzo, “An Outline of Italian Hegelianism (1832–1998),” The Owl of Minerva, 29(1997–1998): 165–205.
Angelica Nuzzo, “Hegel’s Method For a History of Philosophy: The Berlin Introductions to the Lectures on the History of Philosophy,” Hegel’s History of Philosophy: New Interpretations, David A. Duquette, editor, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2003), 19–34.
George Dennis O’Brien, Hegel on Reason and History: A Contemporary Interpretation, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975).
Timothy O’Hagan, “On Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral and Political Philosophy,” Hegel’s Critique of Kant, Stephen Priest, editor, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987), 135–159.
Joseph J. O’Malley, Keith Warren Algozin and Frederick Gustav Weiss, editors, The Legacy of Hegel, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973).
Joseph J. O’Malley, Keith Warren Algozin and Frederick Gustav Weiss, editors, Hegel and the History of Philosophy: Proceedings of the 1972 Hegel Society of America, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974).
John O’Neill, editor, Hegel’s Dialectic of Desire and Recognition: Texts and Commentary, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1996).
Ralph Palm, Hegel’s Concept of Sublation: A Critical Interpretation, Ph.D. Philosophy dissertation, William Desmond, (Leuven: Katholieke Universiteit Leuven, 2009).
Ralph Palm, “Hegel’s Contradictions,” Hegel Bulletin, 31.1–2 (2011): 134–158.
George Henry Radcliffe Parkinson (1923–2015), “Hegel’s Concept of Freedom,” Hegel, Michael Inwood, editor, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985), 153–173.
Allan Patten, Hegel’s Idea of Freedom, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
David Peddle, A Response to M.B. Foster’s Critique of Hegel’s Political Thought, dissertation, (Ottawa: National Library of Canada, 1992).
Zbigniew Andrzej Pełczyński, editor, Hegel’s Political Philosophy: Problems and Perspectives: A Collection of New Essays, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971).
Zbigniew Andrzej Pełczyński, editor, The State and Civil Society: Studies in Hegel’s Political Philosophy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984).
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy (Studies in German Idealism), Reinier Munk, series editor, (Dordrecht: Springer Science+Business Media, B.V., 2001).
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “‘Second Nature’ : Place and Significance of the Objective Spirit in Hegel’s Encyclopedia,” Owl of Minerva, 27.1(Fall, 1995): 51–66.
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “Hegel Contra Hegel in His Philosophy of Right: The Contradiction of International Politics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 32.1(January, 1994): 241–263.
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Philosophy and Politics: A Commentary on the Preface to Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1987).
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “The Foundations of Ethics According to Hegel,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 23(1983): 349–365.
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Philosophy and Politics: A Commentary on the Preface to Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987).
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, Hegels praktische Philosophie: Ein Kommantar zur enzyklopadischen Darstellung der menschlichen Freiheit und ihrer objectiven Verwirklichung, (Stuttgart: Frommann–Holzboog, 1991).
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “L’univers de l’un selon Hegel,” Savoir et Sagesse, (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2011), 79–85.
Adriaan Theodoor Basilius Peperzak, “Some Remarks on Hegel, Kant and Levinas,” Face to Face With Levinas, Richard A. Cohen, editor, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1986), 205– ?
Robert L. Perkins, editor, History and System: Hegel’s Philosophy of History, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1984).
Michael John Petry, editor and translator, “Introduction,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, G.W.F. Hegel, vol. 1, Karl Ludwig Michelet, German editor, forward, (London: George Allen & Unwin, Ltd., 1970), 11–177. [1842–1965]
Terry P. Pinkard, “Hegel’s Idealism and Hegel’s Logic.” Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, 33(April–June, 1979): 210–226.
Terry P. Pinkard, Hegel’s Dialectic: The Explanation of Possibility, (Philadelphia, Pennsylvania: Temple University Press, 1988).
Terry P. Pinkard, Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994).
Terry P. Pinkard and Hugo Tristram Engelhardt, Jr., editors, Hegel Rediscovered: Beyond Metaphysics and the Authoritarian State, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994).
Terry P. Pinkard, Hegel: A Biography, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Robert Buford Pippin, Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self–Consciousness, (Cambridge, Massachucetts: Harvard University Press, 1989).
Robert Buford Pippin, Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Robert Buford Pippin and Otfried Höffe, editors, Hegel on Ethics and Politics, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Robert Buford Pippin, Hegel’s Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency As Ethical Life, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008).
Robert Buford Pippin, Hegel’s Concept of Self–Consciousness, (New Haven: Princeton University Press, 1989).
Andrew Prior, Revolution and Philosophy: The Significance of the French Revolution for Hegel and Marx, (Cape Town, South Africa: D. Philip, 1972).
Otto Pöggeler, “Editorial Introduction,” Lectures on Natural Right and Political Science: The First Philosophy of Right, Heidelberg 1817–1818, With Additions From the Lectures of 1818–1819, G.W.F. Hegel & Peter Wannenmann; J. Michael Stewart & Peter C. Hodgson, editors and translators; Claudia Becker, Wolfgang Bonsiepen, Annemarie Gethmann–Siefert, Friedrich Hogemann, Walter Jaeschke, Christoph Jamme, Hans Christian Lucas, Kurt Rainer Meist & Hans Josef Schneider, Staff of the Hegel Archives editors, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 1–43. [1983 & 1995]
Karl Raimund Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies: The High Tide of Prophecy: Hegel, Marx and the Aftermath, vol. 2, (New York: Harpertorch Books, 1962). [1945]
Stephen Priest, editor, Hegel’s Critique of Kant, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).
Andrew Prior, Revolution and Philosophy: The Significance of the French Revolution For Hegel and Marx, (Capetown: D. Philip, 1972).
Czeslaw Prokopczyk, Truth and Reality in Marx and Hegel: A Reassessment, (Amherst, Massachusetts: University of Massachusetts Press, 1980).
Vijayalakshmi Pandalai Rajiva, Lenin’s Interpretation of Hegel’s Logic, MA Political Science thesis, (Montréal: McGill University, 1981).
Leo Rauch, editor and translator, “Translator’s Introduction,”Introduction to the Philosophy of History, With Selections From the Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, 1988), vii–xiii.
Leo Rauch, editor and translator, “Translator’s Introduction: Note on the Text and Translation,” Introduction to the Philosophy of History, With Selections From the Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, 1988), x–xiii; x–xiii.
Paul Redding, “Philosophical Republicanism and Monarchism―the Republican and Monarchical Philosophy―in Kant and Hegel,” Owl of Minerva, 26.1(Fall, 1994): ?
Paul Redding, Hegel’s Hermeneutics, (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1996).
Hugh Adam Reyburn, The Ethical Theory of Hegel: A Study of the Philosophy of Right, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1921).
Manfred Riedel, Between Tradition and Revolution: The Hegelian Transformation of Political Philosophy, W. Wright, translator, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). [1972]
Giacomo Rinaldi, A History and Interpretation of the Logic of Hegel, (Lewiston, New York: Edwin Mellen, 1992).
David George Ritchie, Darwin and Hegel With Other Philosophical Studies, (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1893).
David George Ritchie, “Hegel’s Early Studies: A Correction,” Mind: New Series, 8(1899): 568.
Joachim Ritter (1903–1974), Hegel and the French Revolution: Essays on the Philosophy of Right (Studies in Contemporary German Social Thought), Richard Dien Winfield, translator, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1982). [1957]
Joachim Ritter, “Person and Property in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (§§34–81),” Hegel on Ethics and Politics, Robert Buford Pippin and Otfried Höffe, editors, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2007), 101–123.
Tom Rockmore, Hegel’s Circular Epistemology, (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1986).
Tom Rockmore, “Foundationalism and Hegelian Logic,” Owl of Minerva, 21.1(Fall, 1989): 41–50.
Tom Rockmore, “Aspects of French Hegelianism,” Owl of Minerva, 24.2(Spring, 1993): 191–206.
Tom Rockmore, On Hegel’s Epistemology and Contemporary Philosophy, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International, 1996).
Tom Rockmore, Cognition: An Introduction to Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1997).
Arthur Kenyon Rogers, “The Absolute of Hegelianism,” Mind: New Series, 9(1900): 332–348.
Arthur Kenyon Rogers, “The Hegelian Conception of Thought,” Philosophical Review, 9(1900): 152–166; 293–310.
David Edward Rose, Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: A Reader’s Guide, (London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2007).
Gillian R. Rose, Hegel Contra Sociology, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1981).
Menahem Rosen, Problems of the Hegelian Dialectic: Dialectic Reconstructed and the Logic of Human Reality, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press, 1992).
Michael Rosen, The Preface to Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, (2000?).
Michael Rosen, Hegel’s Dialectic and Its Criticism, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).
Stanley Rosen, The Idea of Hegel’s “Science of Logic,” (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2013).
Stanley Rosen, G.W.F. Hegel: An Introduction to the Science of Wisdom, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974).
Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz (1805–1879), “Introduction to Hegel’s Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences,” Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Thomas Davidson, translator, 5(1 July 1871): 234–250.
Johann Karl Friedrich Rosenkranz, Hegel As the National Philosopher of Germany, Granville Stanley Hall (1846–1924), translator, (Saint Louis, Missouri: Gray, Baker & Company, 1874).
Michael S. Roth, Knowing and History: The Resurgence of French Hegelianism From 1930 Through the Postwar Period, (New York: De Gruyter, 1988).
Michael S. Roth, Knowing and History: Appropriations of Hegel in Twentieth Century France, (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1988).
Josiah Royce, “Hegel’s Terminology (in Relation to the Hegelian Philosophy),” Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, Including Many of the Principal Conceptions of Ethics, Logic, Aesthetics, Philosophy of Religion, Mental Pathology, Anthropology, Biology, Neurology, Physiology, Economics, Political and Social Philosophy, Philology, Physical Science, and Education, and Giving a Terminology in English, French, German, and Italian, vol. 1, James Mark Baldwin, editor, (New York/London: Macmillan, 1901), 454–465.
Josiah Royce, “Appendix C: The Hegelian Theory of Universals,” The Spirit of Modern Philosophy: An Essay in the Form of Lectures, (Boston/New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1892), 492–506.
Josiah Royce, “Lecture VII: Hegel,” The Spirit of Modern Philosophy: An Essay in the Form of Lectures, (Boston/New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1892), 190–227.
Dagobert David Runes (1902–1982), editor, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: On the Nature of Spirit,” Treasury of Philosophy, Vergilius Ferm, Kurt Friedrich Leidecker and John White, editors, (New York: Philosophical Library, 1955), 474–483.
Bertrand Arthur William Russell (1872–1970), “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” History of Western Philosophy and Its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances From the Earliest Times to the Present Day, (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1947), 757–773. [1946]
John Edward Russon, The Self and Its Body in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, (Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press, 1996).
John Edward Russon, Michael Baur and Henry Silton Harris, editors, Hegel and the Tradition: Essays in Honor of H.S. Harris, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1997).
John Edward Russon, Reading Hegel’s Phenomenology, (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 2004).
Michael G. Salter, editor, Hegel and Law, Seyla Benhabib, Edgar Bodenheimer, Andrew Buchwalter, Markus Dubber, Robert Fine, Abel Garza, Jürgen Habermas, Valerie Kerruish, William N.R. Lucy, Chad McCracken, Patricia Jagentowicz Mills, Gary Minda, Michael G. Salter, Julia Shaw, Peter Stillman, Charles Margrave Taylor, Mark Tunick, Richard Dien Winfield, contributors, (Hants, Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003).
Thomas Collett Sandars (1825–1894), “Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” Oxford Essays, Contributed by Members of the University, (London: John W. Parker and Son, 1855), 213–250.
Andries Sarlemijn, Hegel’s Dialectic, P. Kirschenmann, translator, (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1975). [1971]
Edward L. Schaub, “Hegel’s Criticisms of Fichte’s Subjectivism,” The Philosophical Review, 21.5(1912): 566–584.
G.E. Schulze, (anonymous), “Ænesidemus (excerpt),” Between Kant and Hegel: Texts in the Development of Post–Kantian Idealism, George di Giovanni and H. S. Harris, translators, (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2000), ?
Sylvester Paul Schilling, The Empirical and the Rational in Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion, Ph.D dissertation, (Boston: Boston University Graduate School, 1933–1934).
Dennis J. Schmidt, The Ubiquity of the Finite: Hegel, Heidegger and the Entitlements of Philosophy, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1988).
James Schmidt, “Cabbage Heads and Gulps of Water: Hegel on the Terror,” Political Theory, 26(1998): 4–32.
Carl Schmitt, “Hegel and Marx: German Radio Broadcast of 13 November 1931,” Historical Materialism, 22.3–4(December, 2014): 388–393.
Albert Schwegler, “Hegel,” A History of Philosophy in Outline, 5th edition, Julius H. Seelye, translator, (New York/London: D. Appleton, 1869), 339–365. [1856]
John Waugh Scott (1878–1974), “Neo–Hegelianism,” Encyclopædia of Religion and Ethics: Mundas — Phrygians, vol. 9, James Hastings, John Alexander Selbie and Louis Herbert Gray, editors, (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1917), 300–305. [1913]
Sally Sedgwick, “Hegel’s Critique of the Subjective Idealism of Kant’s Ethics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 26(1988): 89–105.
Sally Sedgwick, editor, “Idealism From Kant to Hegel,” The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 1–18.
Sally Sedgwick, editor, The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
Sally Sedgwick, Hegel’s Critique of Kant: From Dichotomy to Identity, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).
Francis Sedlak, Pure thought and the Riddle of the Universe: Creation of Heaven and Earth, 2 vols., (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1919).
Andrew Seth (Pringle–Pattison), “Hegel: An Exposition and Criticism,” Mind, 6(1881): 513–530.
Andrew Seth, The Development From Kant to Hegel With Chapters on the Philosophy of Religion, (London/Edinburgh: Williams & Norgate, 1882).
Andrew Seth, Hegelianism and Personality: Second Series of Balfour Lectures, (London/Edinburgh: William Blackwood & Sons, 1887).
Andrew Seth, “Hegel and His Recent Critics,” Mind, 14(1889): 116–119.
H.S. Shelton (1876–?), “The Hegelian Concept of the State and Modern Individualism,” International Journal of Ethics, 24(October, 1913): 23–37.
David Sherman, editor, “Introduction,” Hegel’s Phenomenology of Self–Consciousness: Text and Commentary, G.W.F. Hegel; Leo Rauch, translator and commentator, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1999), 1–10.
Rudolf J. Siebert, Hegel’s Philosophy of History: Theological, Humanistic, and Scientific Elements, (Washington, District of Columbia: University Press of America, 1979).
Ludwig Siep, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, Daniel Smyth, translator, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014).
Ludwig Siep, “The Contemporary Relevance of Hegel’s Practical Philosophy,” Hegel: New Directions, Katerina Deligiorgi, editor, (Montreal: McGill–Queen’s University Press, 2006), 143–158. [2003]
Ludwig Siep, “Practical Reason and Spirit in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit,” Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Critical Guide, Dean Moyar & Michael Quante, editors, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), ?
Ludwig Siep, “Recognition in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit and Contemporary Practical Philosophy,” The Philosophy of Recognition: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, Hans–Christoph Schmidt am Busch and Christopher F. Zurn, editors, (New York: Lexington Books, 2010), 107–128.
Thomas Collyns Simon (c.1811–1883), “Hegel and His Connexion With British Thought: Part 1,” The Contemporary Review, 13(January–March, 1870): 47–79.
Thomas Collyns Simon, “Hegel and His Connexion With British Thought: Part 2,” The Contemporary Review, 13(January–March, 1870): 398–421.
Constance I. Smith, “Hegel on War,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 26.2(April–June, 1965): 282–285.
Peter Singer, Hegel, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983).
Steven B. Smith, “Hegel’s Views on War, the State and International Relations,” American Political Science Review, 77.3(September, 1983): 624–632.
Steven B. Smith, “Hegel on Slavery and Domination,” The Review of Metaphysics, 46.1(1992): 97–124.
Steven B. Smith, “What Is ‘Right’ in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right?” The American Political Science Review, 83.1(March, 1989): 3–18.
Elias Hershey Sneath (1857–1935), editor, “Editor’s Prospectus,” The Ethics of Hegel: Translated Selections From His “Rechtsphilosophie” With an Introduction, James Macbride Sterrett (1847–1923), translator, (Boston: Gin & Company, 1893), ?
Ivan Soll, An Introduction to Hegel’s Metaphysics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969).
Robert Solomon, In the Spirit of Hegel, (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983).
Peter Sperber, “Empiricism and Rationalism: The Failure of Kant’s Synthesis and its Consequences for German Philosophy Around 1800,” Kant Yearbook, 7.1(2015): ?
Walter T. Stace, The Philosophy of Hegel, (New York: Dover Publications, 1955).
Peter J. Steinberger, Logic and Politics: Hegel’s Philosophy Right, (New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press, 1988).
Kurt Steinhauer and Gitta Hausen, Hegel Bibliography, 3 vols., (München: K.G. Saur, 1980).
Lawrence S. Stepelevich, editor, The Young Hegelians: An Anthology, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
Lawrence S. Stepelevich and David Lamb, editors, Hegel’s Philosophy of Action, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1983).
Robert Stern, Hegel, Kant and the Structure of the Object, (London: Routledge, 1990).
Robert Stern, editor, G.W.F. Hegel: Critical Assessments, 4 vols., (London/New York: Routledge, 1993).
Robert Stern, Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit, (London: Routledge, 2002).
Robert Stern, The Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Hegel and the Phenomenology of Spirit, (London: Routledge, 2002).
Robert Stern, “Hegel, British Idealism, and the Curious Case of the Concrete Universal,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 15.1(2007): 115–153.
Robert Stern, Hegelian Metaphysics, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
Robert Stern, “Hegel’s Idealism: Hegel as a Kantian Idealist,” Hegelian Metaphysics, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 46–54.
James Macbride Sterrett (1847–1923), translator, “Preface,” The Ethics of Hegel: Translated Selections From His “Rechtsphilosophie” With an Introduction, Elias Hershey Sneath (1857–1935), editor, (Boston: Gin & Company, 1893), vii–viii.
James Macbride Sterrett, translator, “Introduction,” The Ethics of Hegel: Translated Selections From His “Rechtsphilosophie” With an Introduction, Elias Hershey Sneath (1857–1935), editor, (Boston: Gin & Company, 1893), 1–68.
James Macbride Sterrett, Studies in Hegel’s Philosophy of Religion With a Chapter on Christian Unity in America, (New York: D. Appleton, 1890).
Jon Stewart, editor, The Hegel Myths and Legends, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996).
Jon Stewart, editor, “Hegel and the Myth of Reason,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 306–318.
Jon Stewart, “Hegel and the Myth of Reason,” Owl of Minerva, 26(1995): 187–200.
James Hutchison Stirling, The Secret of Hegel: The Hegelian System in Origin, Principle, Form, and Matter, 2 vols., (London: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts and Green, 1865).
James Hutchison Stirling, “The Commentators of Hegel: Schwegler, Rosenkranz, Haym,” The Secret of Hegel: The Hegelian System in Origin, Principle, Form, and Matter, vol. 2, (London: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts and Green, 1865), 398–513.
James Hutchison Stirling, The Secret of Hegel: The Hegelian System in Origin, Principle, Form, and Matter, 2nd edition, 2 vols., (Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd, 1898). [1865]
Wallis Arthur Suchting, Theodore F. Geraets and Henry Silton Harris, editors and translators, “Translators’ Preface,” The Encyclopaedia Logic with the Zusätze: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With the Zusätze, G.W.F. Hegel, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991), vii–ix.
Wallis Arthur Suchting, editor and translator, “Translating Hegel’s Logic: Some Minority Comments on Terminology,” The Encyclopaedia Logic with the Zusatze: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With the Zusatze, G.W.F. Hegel, Henry Silton Harris and Theodore F. Geraets, editors and translators, (Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1991), xxxii–xlviii.
Jere O’Neill Surber, editor, Hegel and Language, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2006).
Charles Margrave Taylor, “The Opening Arguments of the Phenomenology,” Hegel: A Collection of Critical Essays, Alasdair MacIntyre, editor, (New York: Doubleday, 1972), 151–187.
Charles Margrave Taylor, Hegel, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975).
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Sittlichkeit and the Crisis of Representative Institutions,” Philosophy of History and Action, Yirmiyahu Yovel, editor, (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978), 133–154.
Charles Margrave Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979).
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel and the Philosophy of Action,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Action, Lawrence S. Stepelevich and David Lamb, editors, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1983), 1–18.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind,” Contemporary Philosophy: A New Survey, vol. 4, Guttorm Fløristad, editor, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983), 135–155.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel, History and Politics,” Liberalism and Its Critics, Michael J. Sandel, editor, (New York: New York University Press, 1984), 177–199.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind,” Philosophical Papers, vol. 1, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 77–96.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Dialektik heute, oder: Strukturen der Selbsnegation,” Hegels Wissenschaft der Logik: Formation und Rekonstruction, Dieter Henrich, editor, (Stuttgart: Klett–Cotta, 1986), 141–153.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Ambiguous Legacy for Modern Liberalism,” Cardozo Law Review, 10 (1989): 857–870.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Ambiguous Legacy for Modern Liberalism,” Hegel and Legal Theory, Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld and David G. Carlson, editors, (London: Routledge,1991), 64–77.
Charles Margrave Taylor, Multiculturalism and “The Politics of Recognition,” (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1992).
Charles Margrave Taylor, “The Politics of Recognition,” Multiculturalism and the Politics of Recognition, Amy Gutmann, editor, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1992), ?
Charles Margrave Taylor, “The Politics of Recognition,” Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, Amy Gutmann, editor, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1994), ?
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel’s Ambiguous Legacy for Modern Liberalism,” Hegel and Legal Theory, David G. Carlson, Drucilla Cornell & Michel Rosenfeld, editors, (New York: Routledge, 1991), 64–77.
Charles Margrave Taylor, Hegel et la société moderne, (Paris: Cerf, 1998).
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Comment on Jürgen Habermas’ ‘From Kant to Hegel and Back Again,’” European Journal of Philosophy, 7.2(1999): 158–163.
Charles Margrave Taylor, “Hegel and the Social Dynamics of Property Law: Individual Rights Within a Liberal Constitutional Framework: A Necessary But Insufficient Basis For Organizing a Rational State,” Hegel and Law, Michael G. Salter, editor, Seyla Benhabib, Edgar Bodenheimer, Andrew Buchwalter, Markus Dubber, Robert Fine, Abel Garza, Jürgen Habermas, Valerie Kerruish, William N.R. Lucy, Chad McCracken, Patricia Jagentowicz Mills, Gary Minda, Michael G. Salter, Julia Shaw, Peter Stillman, Mark Tunick, Richard Dien Winfield, contributors, (Hants, Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003), ?
Peter Thielke and Yitzhak Y. Melamed, “Hegelianism,” New Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Game Theory to Lysenkoism, vol. 3, Maryanne Cline Horowitz, editor in chief, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 2005), 975–977.
Niels Thulstrup, Kierkegaard’s Relation to Hegel, George L. Stengren, translator, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1980). [1967]
John Edward Toews, Hegelianism: The Path Toward Dialectical Humanism, 1805–1841, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). [1980]
Don Carlos Travis, editor, A Hegel Symposium, (Austin, Texas: University of Texas, 1962).
Don Carlos Travis, editor, “A Philosopher Reconsidered,” A Hegel Symposium, (Austin, Texas: University of Texas, 1962), 3–7.
Colin Tyler, Idealist Political Philosophy: Pluralism and Conflict in the Absolute Idealist Tradition, (London/New York: Continuum Books, 2008). [2006]
Friedrich Ueberweg, “Section 129: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” History of Philosophy From Thales to the Present Day: History of Modern Philosophy, with Additions by the Translator, an Appendix on English and American Philosophy, by Noah Porter, D.D., LL.D., President of Yale College, and an Appendix on Italian Philosophy, by Vincenzo Botta, PH.D., Late Professor of Philosophy in the University of Turin, George Sylvester Morris, translator, (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1873), 231–243.
Augusto Vera (1813–1885), An Introduction to Speculative Philosophy and Logic, (St. Louis, Mo: Gray, Baker & Company, 1875).
Augusto Vera, An Introduction to Speculative Logic and Philosophy, (St. Louis, Mo: R.P. Studley & Company, 1873).
Donald Phillip Verene, Hegel’s Absolute: An Introduction to the Reading of the Phenomenology of Spirit, (Albany, New York: Albany State University of New York, 2007).
Donald Phillip Verene, “Hegel’s Account of War,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, Jon Stewart, editor, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 142–153.
Donald Phillip Verene, editor, Hegel’s Social and Political Thought: The Philosophy of Objective Spirit, (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1980).
Jim Vernon, Hegel’s Philosophy of Language, (London: Continuum, 2007).
John Walker, History, Spirit and Experience: Hegel’s Conception of the Historical Task of Philosophy in His Age, (Frankfurt/New York: Peter Lang, 1995).
William Wallace (1844–1897), Prolegomina to the Study of Hegel’s Philosophy and Especially of His Logic, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1873).
William Wallace, “Preface (1873),” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Prolegomena, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, preface, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1874), v–vii.
William Wallace, “Prolegomena,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Prolegomena, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, preface, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1874), xiii–clxxxiv.
William Wallace, “Prolegomena (Chapter 8): Transition From Kant to Hegel,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Prolegomena, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, preface, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1874), xiii–clxxxiv; lviii–lxiii.
William Wallace, “Prolegomena (Chapter 23): Vocabulary,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Prolegomena, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, preface, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1874), xiii–clxxxiv; clxxv–clxxxiv.
William Wallace, “Note,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1892), v. [1874]
William Wallace, “Bibliographical Notice on the Three Editions and Three Prefaces of the Encyclopaedia,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1892), ix–xxvi. [1874]
William Wallace, “Notes and Illustrations,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1892), 383–431. [1874]
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay I: On the Scope of a Philosophy of Mind,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; xiii–lii.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay II: Aims and Methods of Psychology,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; liii–xciii.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay III: On Some Psychological Aspects of Ethics,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; xciv–cxlv.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay III: On Some Psychological Aspects of Ethics: (ii) Kant, Fichte, and Hegel,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; xciv–cxlv; cvi–cxvi.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay IV: Psycho–Genesis,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; cxlvi–clxxv.
William Wallace, editor and translator, “Five Introductory Essays in Psychology and Ethics, Essay V: Ethics and Politics,” Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind: Translated From the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences With Five Introductory Essays, Hegel; William Wallace, translator, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), xiii–cciv; clxxvi–cciv.
William Wallace, Prolegomina to the Study of Hegel’s Philosophy and Especially of His Logic, 2nd edition, revised and augmented, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894). [1873]
William Wallace, “Note,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1904), v. [1874 & 1892]
William Wallace, “Bibliographical Notice on the Three Editions and Three Prefaces of the Encyclopaedia,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1904), ix–xxvi. [1874 & 1892]
William Wallace, “Notes and Illustrations,” The Logic of Hegel, Translated From the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Hegel; 2nd edition, revised and augmented, William Wallace, translator, bibliographical notice, (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1904), 383–431. [1874 & 1892]
William Wallace, “Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 11th edition, vol. 13, (New York: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1911), 200–207.
William Wallace and James Black Baillie, “Hegel,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1945), 379–381.
William Wallace and James Black Baillie, “Hegelian Philosophy,” Encyclopædia Britannica, 14th edition, vol. 11, (Chicago: Encyclopædia Britannica Inc., 1945), 381–385.
David Walsh, “The Young Hegelians,” Philosophical Studies, 30(1984): 343–345.
William H. Walsh, Hegelian Ethics, (New York: Garland Publishers, 1984).
Steven Walt, “Hegel on War: Another Look,” The Hegel Myths and Legends, Jon Stewart, editor, (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1996), 167–182.
Nicholas Walter, “Hegel in the Mirror of Biography: On the Biographical Hegel–Literature From Rosenkranz to Althaus,” Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 27/28(1993): 1–11.
Andrzej Warminski, Readings in Interpretation: Hölderlin, Hegel, Heidegger, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987).
Thomas E. Wartenburg, “Hegel’s Idealism: The Logic of Conceptuality,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, Frederick C. Beiser, editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 102–129.
Norbert Waszek, The Scottish Enlightenment and Hegel’s Account of “Civil Society,” (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publications, 1988).
David Watson, “The Neo–Hegelian Tradition in America,” Journal of American Studies, 14(1980): 219–234.
John Watson, “The Problem of Hegel,” Philosophical Review, 3(1894): 546–567.
Eric Weil, Hegel and the State, Mark A. Cohen, translator, (Baltimore, Maryland: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998).
Frederick G. Weiss, editor, Beyond Epistemology: New Studies in the Philosophy of Hegel, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1974).
Kenneth R. Westphal, “Hegel’s Critique of Kant’s Moral World View,” Philosophical Topics, 19.2(1991): 133–175.
Kenneth R. Westphal, “The Basic Context and Structure of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,” The Cambridge Companion to Hegel, Frederick C. Beiser, editor, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 234–269.
Kenneth R. Westphal, Hegel’s Epistemological Realism: A Study of the Aim and Method of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989).
Kenneth R. Westphal, “Kant, Hegel, and the Fate of the ‘Intuitive Intellect,’” The Reception of Kant’s Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, Sally Sedgwick, editor, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 283–305.
Merold Westphal, “Dialectic and Intersubjectivity,” The Owl of Minerva, 16(1984): ?
Merold Westphal, History and Truth in Hegel’s “Phenomenology,” (New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1982). [1978]
Merold Westphal, Hegel, Freedom, and Modernity, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1992).
Franz Wiedmann, Hegel: An Illustrated Biography, Joachim Neugroschel, translator, (New York: Pegasus, 1968).
Burleigh Taylor Wilkins, “James, Dewey, and Hegelian Idealism,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 17(1956): 332–346.
Burleigh Taylor Wilkins, Hegel’s Philosophy of History, (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1974).
Robert R. Williams, Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the Other, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1992).
Robert R. Williams, “Ludwig Siep’s Studies of Hegel’s Practical Philosophy,” Hegel’s Ethics of Recognition, (Berkeley, California: University of California Press, 1997), 19–22.
Robert R. Williams, Hegel’s Ethics of Recognition, (Berkeley, California: University of California Press, 1998). [1997]
Robert R. Williams, editor, Beyond Liberalism and Communitarianism: Studies in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2001).
Robert R. Williams, editor and translator, “Translator’s Introduction,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit: 1827–1828, G.W.F. Hegel, Johann Erdmann and Ferdinand Walter; Pierre Garniron, Franz Hespe, Walter Jaeschke and Burkhard Tuschling, German and French editors, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), 1–56. [1989–1994–1996]
Robert R. Williams, editor and translator, “Introduction,” Lectures on the Philosophy of Spirit: 1827–1828, G.W.F. Hegel, Johann Erdmann and Ferdinand Walter; Pierre Garniron, Franz Hespe, Walter Jaeschke and Burkhard Tuschling, German and French editors, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), 57–79. [1989–1994–1996]
Raymond Jackson Wilson, “Dewey’s Hegelianism,” History of Education Quarterly, 15.1(Spring, 1975): 87–92.
Richard Dien Winfield, “Identity, Difference and the Unity of Mind, Reflections on Hegel’s Determination of Psyche, Consciousness and Intelligence,” Identity and Difference: Studies in Hegel’s Logic and Politics, Philip Grier, editor, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2007), ?
Allen W. Wood, “Hegel’s Concept of Morality,” J.V. Snellmanin Filosofia ja sen Hegelilainen Tausta, I. Patoluoto, editor, (Helsinki, 1984).
Allen W. Wood, “Does Hegel Have an Ethics,” The Monist, 74.3(July, 1991): 358–385.
Allen W. Wood, editor, “Editor’s Introduction,” Elements of the Philosophy of Right, G.W.F. Hegel; Hugh Barr Nisbet, translator, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), vii–xxxii. [1991]
Allen W. Wood, Hegel’s Ethical Thought, (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
Allen W. Wood, “The Emptiness of the Moral Will,” Monist, 72(1989): 454–483.
Jon Woronoff, series editor, “Forward,” Historical Dictionary of Hegelian Philosophy, John W. Burbidge, 2nd edition, (Lanham, Maryland: The Scarecrow Press, 2008), xi–xii.
André Wylleman, editor, Hegel on Ethical Life: Religion and Philosophy, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989).
James Yerkes, The Christology of Hegel, (Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 1983).
Yirmiyahu Yovel, editor, Philosophy of History and Action, (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978).
Yirmiyahu Yovel, Dark Riddle: Hegel, Nietzsche, and the Jews, (Cambridge: Polity Press/University Park: Penn State University Press, 1998).
Yirmiyahu Yovel, translator and commentator, “Introduction,” Hegel’s Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 2005), 1–62.
Hua Xue and Xue–Mei Xue, “Information on Hegel Studies and Editions in China,” Owl of Minerva, 18.1(Fall, 1986): 92–95.
©2016–2017–2018 Christopher Richard Wade Dettling, Americanism: Stronghold of Hegel (2013–2018). All rights reserved. This work is only for MEDIUM and the MEDIUM CORPORATION and its users: Users are not permitted to mount this writing on any network servers. No part of this writing may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the author, except for reading and browsing via the World Wide Web.
We wish to thank our benefactors over the years for their goodwill: Humanity benefits greatly from the rise of Americanism in the world.