Monetary Properties

Beyond Aristotelian Money

Mirelo
Privately Concrete Money Versus Metamoney
4 min readOct 26, 2013

--

According to Aristotle, money must have the following properties:

  1. Durability
  2. Portability
  3. Divisibility
  4. Intrinsic value

Intrinsic Monetary Value

So Aristotle regarded intrinsic value—the exchange value money would always have even without being money—as a property without which money became impossible, or at least unsound. However, not only his idea of sound money was wrong as it was also the opposite of the truth: intrinsic value is precisely what makes money unsound. To understand why, let us begin by defining money in the least controversial way possible:

Money is anything accepted as payment for goods and services and repayment of debts.

Then, let us notice the different meanings that money being “accepted as payment for goods and services and repayment of debts” has to buyers or debt redeemers and sellers or creditors:

  1. To sellers and creditors, it means their accepting the money respectively of buyers and debt redeemers.
  2. To buyers and debt redeemers, it means the acceptance of their money respectively by sellers and creditors.

Finally, let us notice that any buyers or debt redeemers ignoring the acceptance of their money respectively by sellers and creditors would be the same as the lack of that acceptance. Money must already be known even by merely possible buyers and debtors to be “accepted as payment for goods and services and repayment of debts”: it must be socially rather than individually accepted as money. Then, we can complete its definition:

Money is anything accepted as payment for goods and services and repayment of debts, as long as already known even by merely possible buyers and debtors to be so.

From Aristotle to Adam Smith to Marx to Milton Friedman, we have never made such a distinction between accepting money and knowing about its acceptance by others. Instead, by assuming that monetary acceptance does not require its own social awareness, we have long been sharing the false belief on individually rather than socially accepted money.

While, despite acceptance depending on evaluation, the resulting absence of any actual (socially accepted) form of money makes monetary evaluation unnecessary, whether by sellers, buyers, creditors, or debt redeemers. This possible absence of any evaluation of money then reduces its required exchange value to an intrinsic property of the monetary object itself, hence to just another preexisting reason for its acceptance as money—Aristotle’s “intrinsic” monetary value.

So requiring money to have an intrinsic value results from confusing between individually and socially accepted money: actual monetary value requires no longer individual but instead already social (reciprocally aware) acceptance of its own representation by an object, being thus never intrinsic to that object.

Indeed, monetary history overwhelmingly shows that anything can be money, whether being otherwise valuable or not. So whoever advocates “intrinsic value” as a means of “restoring” monetary soundness must either completely abandon that idea or find something else to “back” it—other than the requirement for money to have such an extrinsic monetary value.

Beyond Aristotle

Additionally, since Aristotle, money has conceptually acquired a myriad of new required properties, like transmissibility, fungibility, or scarcity.

Transmissibility

The idea of money being transmissible was alien to Aristotle. This is because money was to him just a physical object, something usually portable but hardly transmissible. Today, money can be a number electronically or optically recorded, something both portable and electronically or optically transmissible.

Fungibility

Unlike transmissibility, fungibility was not alien to Aristotle, despite absent from his required monetary properties. It only means that money must not vary qualitatively, but only quantitatively.

Scarcity

Scarcity was also not alien to Aristotle, despite absent from his required monetary properties. It only means that money must be hard enough to find or produce for preventing the monetary unit from losing value too rapidly, if ever.

Relative Monetary Requirements

Finally, there are historical examples of money partially lacking not only transmissibility, but also each single one of Aristotle’s three first required monetary properties (durability, portability, and divisibility), or even fungibility—as in sea shells or feathers—and scarcity—as in bank notes. Indeed:

  1. All those properties are quantifiable.
  2. Money must have only a minimum of durability, portability, divisibility, transmissibility, fungibility, and scarcity, variable according to social development—and sometimes negligible, like the transmissibility of sheer gold.

The quantitatively variable nature of those properties makes them relative monetary requirements. Other such requirements include making theft or counterfeiting difficult and storage easy, none of which mentioned by Aristotle.

Absolute Monetary Requirement

There is only one absolute monetary requirement: money must be publicly private.

Public Privacy

This requirement was not alien to Aristotle, despite absent from his required monetary properties. It only means that monetary value must be private while its representing object must be public. A physical object can only partially meet this requirement since it cannot itself distinguish monetary value from its then-physical representation, which makes any such object privately public—in addition to falsely making its monetary value intrinsic to it.[1] Only today, with public-key cryptography, can Bitcoin-like money be publicly private without being privately public, by representing monetary value as a private key then metarepresenting it as the corresponding public key—to become what in my book Representational Monetary Identity I call a metarepresented money, or metamoney.

  1. Intrinsic monetary value is what Marx called commodity “Fetishism.”

--

--