What is is?

The post-modern tendency to strip meaning from the world is unconsciously rooted in the socratic philosophical mistake of disallowing the being of anything that isn’t a self-sufficient substance.

Andrew Bindon
#Social #3D #VR #MR #mind_mapping #app
13 min readOct 18, 2018

--

If you don’t strip the world of its meaning in the first place, you don’t have to find a way of putting the meaning back.

https://thort.space/journey/110898789587140112950_4770908987140461382_4761598985556014761/1

To see the Heideggerian / BeingAndTime perspective on this, in the expression “the world we live in is innately meaningful” you have to be able to underline “we live in”. Western academia and “commonsense” has been seduced by socratic substance ontology, which was turned into subject-object ontology by Descartes.

If you start from substance ontology you end up with 2000 years of philosophical befuddlement (“the problem of the external world”, “the problem of other minds”, scepticism , anti-realism, etc.) and with a world that is empty and meaningless (and empty and meaningless that it is empty and meaningless). Part of Heidegger’s genius was to see that we aren’t obliged to do that.

Set YouTube quality to 1080p (via the Cog) or visit Thortspace for live content: https://thort.space/journey/110898789587140112950_4770908987140461382_4761598985556014761/1
For the best experience, view YouTube videos at the highest available resolution.

This is a talk about my understanding of Division 1 of Heidegger’s Being and Time, which I have mostly gleaned from reading and listening to commentaries rather than by studying the original text.

The commentaries that I have found most helpful are listed on the last slide in the presentation.

Underneath each of the Thortspace graphics, there is a link to a step of a Thortspace journey that corresponds to that graphic. So you can hop off the journey and travel forwards and backwards along it, zoom out, browse around, and then come back here for more orienting text. There are links from each Thort group back to the corresponding place in this Medium article, too. (I used this article to figure out how to link to specific places within a Medium article.)

We tend to assume we know what these little words are doing, and what they mean. But Heidegger thinks that we don’t know what they are doing or what they mean with anything like the degree of clarity which a subject as important as this one deserves. [Heidegger calls this our “forgetfulness of being”.]

Let’s say a being is an entity — perhaps any entity at all. An object, a subject, a number, a god or The God, an event, a process, a person, you, me, them, a work of art, equipment, a mental state. As a first approximation, we can say that any entity that is, is a being. So Heidegger’s question is: what is it to be a being? What does it mean to be a being? Ok, we know what beings are, but what is being itself? That is to say, what is is?

As an aside, let’s distinguish two types of knowing:

Knowing that: I know that the earth orbits the sun. I know that F=ma. I know that the rules of football are xyz. I know the highway code in the UK requires you to drive less than 30 mph where there are streetlights unless there is signage to tell you otherwise.

Knowing how: My friend Caroline knows how to use a telescope. I know how to ride a bicycle. I know how to drive a car.

Returning to the question of being, the philosophical tradition either says or assumes that to be is to be a substance; and two things determine what it is to be a substance:
(1) The being of substances is self-sufficient — independent of circumstances, environments and human contexts. Everything that it means to be a given lump of gold is supposedly contained within that lump of gold. A lump of gold sitting on my desk contains all of its properties and does not depend for anything outside itself to have those properties. A lump of gold could presumably still be what it is, even if the rest of the world was suddenly deleted from the universe.
(2) The properties of substances are themselves thought of as being somehow self-sufficient / self-contained / independent of other properties.

At least according to Heidegger, the philosophical tradition conceptualises all being as self-sufficient substances expressing self-sufficient properties. What it is to be a being is to be a self-sufficient substance. Thinkers don’t necessarily need to think this for Heidegger’s assertion to be valid. It could just be that everything thinkers think is consistent with this conceptualisation of being. In other words, we assume that being is self-sufficient substances, and everything we think is consistent with that.

Instead of relying on our pre-conceived conceptualisation of what being is, Heidegger thinks we should base our conceptualisation on our ground-level, basic, everyday experience of being beings in the world which we are familiar with — as we go about our day to day business.

This does seem reasonable. If we want a conceptualisation that is consistent with regular day-to-day experience, a conceptualisation which does not lead to conclusions that we find jarring, it makes a kind of sense to use that day-to-day experience as our starting place.

An alternative starting point that has been suggested is to use the scientific method. Surely, the argument goes, an objective viewpoint, which has all human biases and purposes cleared away from it, is a better starting point for understanding the nature of our world.

How should we understand what science is, or how science works? By doing more science, of course! People who advocate this viewpoint think of this approach as a virtuous circle, but probably they are wrong.

Before saying what Heidegger wants to tell us that being is, lets say what Heidegger wants to tell us that being is not.

Being is not a being, and especially not the supreme being. Being is not beingness. Being is not only self-sufficient substances.

Heidegger is willing to grant that one type of being is self-sufficent substances. But he sees self-sufficient substances as being only one kind out of several types of being, and possibly a fairly impoverished kind of being compared to the other two types which we’re coming on to.

Heidegger says on page 150 : “being is that on the basis of which, beings are already understood”.

However the rest of the text makes it clear that when Heidegger says “understood” here, he is not talking about understood in a cognitive way. He is not talking about “know-that”. Rather he is talking about “know-how”. He is talking about the way our actions and experience have an <<<already having made-sense of the situation we are in>>> built into them — an embedded intelligibility — analogously like water is to a fish — although as we will see shortly, Heidegger thinks we swim in three different kinds of water.

So Heidegger thinks we have two kinds of “taken-for-granted”:

We have a taken-for-granted way of conceptualizing the world, and we have a taken-for-granted way of behaving in and experiencing the world — and the first of these is not consistent with the second of these.

Heidegger thinks the first of these assumes that there is one kind of being — namely self-sufficient substances. And the second of these implies three kinds of being, which are described on the next slide.

In Being and Time Heidegger thinks that there are at least 2 other kinds of being besides self-sufficient substances: namely equipment and ourselves.

The first thing to pin down about these types of being is most importantly that neither of them are self-sufficient substances.

As human beings, we experience and grasp the world in its totality in a way that is prior to, and more significant than, any experience of substances or equipment or each other. Experience and behaviour make sense only at the level of the whole situation and situatedness. It is possible for us to isolate beings within the wholeness of our experience and separate these entities from the world they are given by — ie. to travel from the whole to some part. But the idea that we could construct the wholeness of our experience from isolated pieces of experience is not viable, not if we give the phenomena of our experience their due attention.

My favourite example to illustrate how equipment occurs in a way that is quite distinct from substances, is the clutch pedal on a manual geared car. But you can use just about any piece of equipment that you like. Those of us who drive manual geared cars, know that we use the clutch pedal every time we change gear. When you were first learning how to drive, it was a big deal pushing the clutch down at the right time, and releasing it to engage the gear. Now when you drive to the shops and back it is barely something you even notice. So the first phenomenon to notice about equipment is that it becomes transparent as our compentence increases.

Another thing to notice is that the clutch pedal is significant only in respect of its role in driving your car, and your car is only useful because there is a road network to drive it on. And none of this would have any kind of significance if you didn’t want to go places. So Heidegger wants us to consider that the being of equipment is an equipmental totality in which all equipment has its place, only by virtue of all other equipment. And this equipmental totality is only significant because it meshes with human activity.

Couldn’t we just add function-properties to substances to get equipment. No, not if we want to genuinely and adequately capture the phenomena of equipment as equipment actually is for us in our day-to-day experience.

The experience of being ourselves is typically not the “me in-here / external world out-there” conception that the philosophical tradition likes to assume. You only get to have that kind of experience when you go somewhere unfamiliar. For most of us, most of the time, we find ourselves out in the world and engaged in activities. Heidegger says we experience ourselves as the world in which we are living — we are always already in-the-world, familiar with our world and being that world.

Being-in-the-world is not the relationship of one object being inside another object — rather it is simply familiarity. My computer is in my office, but it doesn’t experience the office as “my” office in the way that I do. If I take my iPad to work in the Borough Gardens I experience the gardens as my local park… not because I legally own the park, but because I am familiar with it. This kind of mineness / being-in / familiarity mostly goes unnoticed and comes to our attention only by its absense — when I go places I am not familiar with and feel the consequent sense of disorientation.

Heidegger points out that the phenomenology of “dasein” destroys any coherent distinction between self and world. The phenomena of dasein is wholstic. Dasein is its world.

Dasein is the being whose being is a concern/issue for itself. Heidegger calls this condition “existence”. (Kierkegard says: “The self is a relation that relates itself to itself.”) But noting that “dasein is its world” — we can conclude that dasein is a world of significance that is concerned about its own significance.

So the transformation in our thinking that Heidegger is advocating is to move from a conceptualisation of being in which all beings are self-sufficient substances (and since everything is that, the question mostly doesn’t even arise or occur to anyone), to a conceptualisation in which there are multiple types of being (in B&T Heidegger basically thinks there are 3 types). Since these types of being each have a unique conceptualisation, which in the case of both equipment and ourselves is wholistic, we can see how we might have previously been getting confused when we conceptualised all beings as though they are self-sufficient substances.

So what’s the big deal about wholism? The thing that is significant about wholistic perspectives is not that the whole is greater than the sum of that parts.

“That’s true about a pile of bricks, the whole is greater than the sum of the parts. That’s not interesting.” Hubert Dreyfus.

The significant thing about wholistic perspectics is that the whole makes the part what it is. The meaning of the part is the consequence of being a part of the whole that it is a part of.

So roughly speaking Heidegger is saying that the reason why philosophers find the world so confusing and paradoxical, is because they have conceptualised the world in an incorrect way at a very basic level. And when you follow the implications of that fundamental conceptual error through to its conclusions, you get all kinds of paradoxes.

It is a fundamental misunderstanding that:
(1) firstly all beings are substances and that
(2a) secondly self can be easily separated from the wholism it shares with the world, and that
(2b) thirdly equipment can be easily isolated from the equipmental totality or easily understood as objects with properties.

Heidegger thinks these three inadequate assumptions are shaping our thinking without us realising it, and consequently giving rise to baffling philosophical puzzles.

Consequently Heidegger is advocating using the phenomena of day-to-day experience as the basis on which to construct our fundamental understandings of being.

Once we stop putting the square pegs of equipment and ourselves into the round hole of self-sufficient substances, we are freed up to understand these other types of being in terms of the wholistic phenomena as it actually presents itself to us. And consequently the conceptualisation we draw from this, and conclusions we draw from that conceptualisation, are much easier to square with the phenomena of our everyday lives that we are basing them on.

Having established the world we experience and act in as being characterised by these three distinct kinds of being, Heidegger goes on to illucidate science as being a process of using skilful activity to isolate self-sufficient substances by means of ready-to-hand equipment and resources.

https://thort.space/journey/110898789587140112950_4770908987140461382_4761598985556014761/23

This slide is a technical detail which some club members may find interesting but probably not central to the talk I’m giving.

Substances are more causally fundamental. You can’t make a hammer out of jelly or pillows or hay.

But equipement is more fundamental in respect of inteligibility. You can’t understand what it is to be a hammer merely from the causal properties of the materials used to make one.

For the best experience on YouTube videos, turn the resolution up to the maximum available.
Andrew is a Product Designer at Thortspace, the world’s first collaborative 3D mind mapping software. Thortspace enables breakthrough collaborative thinking whenever and wherever it is needed most. More stories here.

--

--

Andrew Bindon
#Social #3D #VR #MR #mind_mapping #app

Andrew is a Product Designer at https://medium.com/thortspace - #3D #VR #collaborative #thought_mapping #app. See it more than one way!